t ^onsirucmg tne oUDjec t.Mne Hesearcn Heiationsnip in interperso n Cultural History as Transformation— or, What's the Matter with Ps 1 he Miss nd the [ nd the f e Meta nd Be\ Interps atter w istory o 'estern f Psych the His f Const Cultu undt a he Mis; nd the nd the e Meta nd Bey( Interpc atter w istory o Western | Psych the Hi; f Const undt a he Mis; nd the nd the e Meta nd L Psy HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF PSYCHOLOGY Series Editor: Man Cheung Chung REDISCOVERING THE HISTORY OF PSYCHOLOGY Essays Inspired by the Work of Kurt Danziger Edited by Adrian C. Brock Johann Louw and Willem van Hoorn IOI lull I Ul L/l// l*JLI L/C n Ps uictii Sea /leth The isfo iThei Psy he f ojec ige: Exp erso i Ps Psy i Ps ictii Sea /Is The TSfO n Psy :he F eiec txp ersoi Iptfi Interpersonal Areas of Psychology • On Cultural Histoi i Ibl 1 A f Rediscovering the History of Psychology Essays Inspired by the Work of Kurt Danziger HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF PSYCHOLOGY Series Editor: Man Cheung Chung, University of Plymouth, Plymouth, United Kingdom DESTINED FOR DISTINGUISHED OBLIVION The Scientific Vision of William Charles Wells (1757-1817) Nicholas J. Wade REDISCOVERING THE HISTORY OF PSYCHOLOGY Essays Inspired by the Work of Kurt Danziger Edited by Adrian C. Brock, Johann Louw, and Willem van Hoorn A Continuation Order Plan is available for this series. A continuation order will bring delivery of each new volume immediately upon publication. Volumes are billed only upon actual shipment. For further information please contact the publisher. Rediscovering the History of Psychology Essays Inspired by the Work of Kurt Danziger Edited by Adrian C. Brock University College Dublin Dublin, Ireland Johann Louw University of Cape Town South Africa Willem van Hoorn University of Amsterdam Amsterdam, Netherlands KLUWER ACADEMIC PUBLISHERS NEW YORK, BOSTON, DORDRECHT, LONDON, MOSCOW eBook ISBN: 0-306-48031-X Print ISBN: 0-306-47906-0 ©2005 Springer Science + Business Media, Inc. Print ©2004 Kluwer Academic/Plenum Publishers New York All rights reserved No part of this eBook may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, recording, or otherwise, without written consent from the Publisher Created in the United States of America Visit Springer's eBookstore at: and the Springer Global Website Online at: http://ebooks.springerlink.com http://www.springeronline.com CONTRIBUTORS Betty M. Bayer is Associate Professor of Social Psychology in Women’s Studies at Hobart and William Smith Colleges, Geneva, New York, USA. Richard Walsh-Bowers is Professor of Psychology at Wilfred Laurier University, Waterloo, Ontario, Canada. Adrian C. Brock is College Lecturer in Psychology at University College Dublin, Ireland. Kurt Danziger is Professor Emeritus of Psychology at York University, Toronto, Canada and Honorary Professor of Psychology at the University of Cape Town, South Africa. Willem van Hoorn is Professor Emeritus of Psychology at the University of Amsterdam, Netherlands and Honorary Professor of Psychology at the University of Cape Town, South Africa. Johann Louw is Professor and Head of the Department of Psychology at the University of Cape Town, South Africa. Hans van Rappard has taught history and systems of psychology at the Free University, Amsterdam, Netherlands. He now studies comparative philosophy. Irmingard Staeuble is Professor of Psychology at the Free University, Berlin, Germany. Henderikus J. Stam is Professor of Psychology at the University of Calgary, Canada. Pieter J. van Strien is Professor Emeritus of Theory and History of Psychology at Groningen University, Netherlands and former President of the Archives of Dutch Psychology (ADNP). Andrew S. Winston is Professor of Psychology at the University of Guelph, Ontario, Canada. CONTENTS Introduction 1 Adrian C. Brock 1. Reconstructing the Subject: Kurt Danziger and the Revisionist Project in Historiographies of Psychology 19 Henderikus J. Stam 2. In Search of Method 33 Johann Louw 3. Controlling the Metalanguage: Authority and Acquiescence in the History of Method 53 Andrew S. Winston 4. Paris, Leipzig, Danziger, and Beyond 75 Pieter J. van Strien 5. Expanding the Terrain of Constructing the Subject: The Research Relationship in Interpersonal Areas of Psychology 97 Richard Walsh-Bowers 6. On Cultural History as Transformation — or, What’s the Matter with Psychology Anyway? Betty M. Bayer vii 119 CONTENTS viii 7. Wundt as an Activity/Process Theorist: An Event in the History of Psychological Thinking 141 Hans van Rappard 8. The Missing Link of Historical Psychology 161 Willem van Hoorn 9. De-Centering Western Perspectives: Psychology and the Disciplinary Order in the First and Third World 183 Irmingard Staeuble 10. Concluding Comments 207 Kurt Danziger Appendix: Kurt Danziger ’s Publications 233 Index 239 INTRODUCTION 1 Adrian C. Brock BACKGROUND AND AIMS OF THIS BOOK The three editors of this book are all related to Kurt Danziger in different ways. I was a PhD student with him at York University in Toronto from 1988 to 1993 and we have stayed in regular contact ever since. Johann Louw is based at the University of Cape Town where Danziger is a regular visitor. Willem van Hoorn, who was Louw’s PhD supervisor at the University of Amsterdam, is also a regular visitor to the University of Cape Town. The three of us came together out of a mutual admiration for Danziger’ s work. When we began to discuss the possibility of producing a book on Danziger’s work, we were agreed that we did not want to produce a ‘Festschrift’ in the tra- ditional sense of the term. There is, of course, no harm in producing such a book but we thought that there could be no greater tribute to Danziger than to make his work the focal point for a variety of contributions representing several areas of active research in history and theory of psychology. Although in recent years productive scholarship has flourished in this field (Richards, 2002a), this situation is not reflected in the readily available literature. There are few broad discussions of the current state of history and theory of psychology, as well as its problems and future directions. For obvious reasons, scholars in this field tend to focus on the limited aspect of the history of psychology that forms the topic of their research. The essays in this volume will go some way towards filling this gap. They range in scope from the role of history and theory of psychology in the discipline of psychology, the marginalization of cultural- historical approaches to psychology, historical psychology and its relationship to history and theory of psychology, the epistemological implications of critical history, the inclusion of parts of the world other than Europe and North America 1 2 ADRIAN C. BROCK in psychology’s history, the future of academic disciplines and much more. As such, the essays in this volume can serve as a departure point for those who wish to acquaint themselves with some of the most important issues in the field. KURT DANZIGER’S WORK Kurt Danziger has had a long career in psychology, having been awarded his DPhil from the University of Oxford in 1952. The research for his dissertation involved standard 1940s laboratory experiments using rats (e.g. Danziger, 1953). He had already become critical of this kind of research while he was writing his dissertation and he subsequently began to do Piagetian-style research with children (e.g. Danziger, 1958). However, his interests moved towards social psychology during the 1950s and this area of psychology became his main research interest until the end of the 1970s. His work in this area includes a well-known study of the sociology of knowledge in South Africa (Danziger, 1963) and books on Socialization (Danziger, 1971) and Interpersonal Communication (1976). While much of this work is highly original and of continuing interest to researchers in this field (see Louw, this volume), the focus of this book is the work on history and theory of psychology that Danziger started to publish in 1979. Danziger’s switch to history and theory of psychology began when he had a sabbatical in academic 1973-74. He decided to use the sabbatical to acquaint himself with the original works of some of the important figures in the early history of psychology. His knowledge of German was an obvious advantage in this task as he read the work of Helmholtz, Fechner, Wundt, and many less prominent authors. Danziger compared his situation on reading these works to that of a subject in an Asch conformity experiment since the views that were being expressed in the original works of these authors bore little or no relationship to the views that had been traditionally attributed to them. At first, he wondered if he was misunderstanding these works but it became increasingly clear that there was a discrepancy between the primary and secondary sources (Brock, 1995a; 1995b). It is difficult for those of us who were not involved in history and theory of psychology in the 1970s to imagine how undeveloped the field was at this time. Although history and theory of psychology had been an active area of pedagogy for many years, it had only become a recognized area of research in the United States in the late 1960s with the establishment of the American Psychological Association’s Division 24 (Theoretical/Philosophical Psychology) and Division 26 (History of Psychology), as well as the Cheiron Society (International Society for the History of the Behavioral and Social Sciences), the Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences and the graduate program in history and theory of psychology at the University of New Hampshire (Ash, 1983; Brock, 1998). It was to be several more years before it became well established in other countries. INTRODUCTION 3 Danziger’s move into history and theory of psychology in the early 1970s was a part of this wider trend. The establishment of history and theory of psychology as an active area of research had several important consequences for the field. As Danziger’s account of his reaction on reading the original works of important figures in the history of psychology shows, many historical ‘facts’ that had been merely taken for granted up to that point were challenged. Revisionist accounts of several important figures and events in the history of psychology began to appear and criticism of the standard accounts of psychology’s history in the authoritative works by Boring (1950) and Allport (1985) was a central feature of what came to be known as ‘critical history of psychology’ (Danziger, 1984). Moreover, it was clear that the standard accounts of psychology’s history helped to reinforce mainstream psychology and so revisionist history became a way of attempting to change the discipline itself. Both of these points can be seen in what may be Danziger’s best-known early work in this field, “The positivist repudiation of Wundt” (Danziger, 1979a). The standard view in American accounts up to that point was that the former student of Wundt, E. B. Titchener was a loyal disciple who had represented Wundt’s views in the United States. This view had its origins in the text of Boring (1950) but Titchener’s devotion to Wundt had been exaggerated even further by later writ- ers (Brock, 1993). Danziger drove a wedge between the two by pointing out that Titchener had been influenced by the positivist epistemology of Mach, something that he had in common with Wundt’s renegade student, Oswald Ktilpe who sub- sequently founded the Wurzburg School. Danziger’s account was based on sound historical scholarship but it can also be seen that he was enlisting Wundt’s anti- positivist views in support of his own. These themes were expanded in another article in the Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences in the following year, “The history of introspection reconsidered” (Danziger, 1980a). The title is taken from a paper by Boring titled, “The history of introspection” (Boring, 1953) and clearly shows Danziger’s crit- ical and revisionist aims. Another early work that deserves mention is a book chapter, “The social origins of modern psychology” that was published as part of a collection on ‘sociology of psychological knowledge’ since it shows the con- tinuity between Danziger’s early work on the sociology of knowledge in South Africa and his later historical and theoretical work (Danziger, 1963; 1979b; see also Louw, this volume). This chapter shows Danziger’s familiarity with the so- ciology of science and includes a critique of the application of role theory in this area. A sociological orientation can also be seen in some of his later historical and theoretical work so that at times he has had to defend himself against the mistaken charge of ‘sociological reductionism’ (Danziger, 1992a; 1993a; see also Stam, this volume). The years 1979/80 were important for the establishment of history and theory of psychology as a recognized sub-speciality within the discipline. According 4 ADRIAN C. BROCK to the traditional account of Boring (1950), the discipline of psychology could trace its origins to the establishment of Wundt’s laboratory at the University of Leipzig in 1879. Psychologists as a whole are not generally interested in the history of their field but anniversaries are an exception to the rule and there was no bigger anniversary than the establishment of psychology itself. The American Psychological Association declared 1979 to be psychology’s centennial year and the International Congress of Psychology, which is held every four years, moved to Leipzig in 1980 in order to commemorate the event. In spite of the dubious historical accuracy of this account, the anniversary provided many opportunities to publish historical work on Wundt and to have it widely read. Danziger contributed three chapters to two special volumes on the legacy of Wundt and an article in a special issue of Psychological Research that was devoted to Wundt (Danziger, 1980b; 1980c; 1980d; 1980e). As a result, he came to be regarded as one of the foremost Wundt-scholars in the field. Danziger’s work on Wundt declined sharply in quantity during the 1980s. I am aware of only two works on the subject that he published during this decade and both appear to have been commissioned (Danziger, 1983; 1988). Following the ‘centennial’ period, there was a change in Danziger’s research interests to- wards psychological methodology and its history (e.g. Danziger, 1985a; 1985b). However, this interest was already apparent during the earlier period (Danziger, 1980e). The topic of methodology is central to psychology’s history because of the theoretical divisions that became apparent in the early years of the discipline. The 1920s are sometimes characterized as ‘the age of schools’ and the theoreti- cal diversity that existed was outlined by authors such as Woodworth (1931) and Heidbreder (1933). This kind of theoretical diversity is common in the human or social sciences, such as sociology, linguistics and anthropology, but psychologists were looking towards physics and the other natural sciences as a model for the discipline and described this situation as a ‘crisis’ (Driesch, 1926; Biihler, 1965; Vygotsky, 1985). It did not help the position of psychology in society since psy- chologists could hardly address the public from a position of authority if they could not agree among themselves. When psychology finally achieved some degree of unity after the Second World War, it was not on theoretical but on methodological grounds. A strict set of methodological rules was established in the United States and subsequently exported to other parts of the world. It was these methods that came to define the field. The topic of ‘mind’ had been established for centuries as an object of phi- losophy and it was part of the discourse of society at large. Even ‘behavior’ could not be seen as the exclusive preserve of psychology since it was appropriated by a range of disciplines describing themselves as ‘the behavioral sciences’. There- fore, the special contribution of psychology came to be defined not in terms of its subject matter but in terms of its methods. Even though many of these methods were unique to psychology (Winston, this volume), they were legitimated by an INTRODUCTION 5 appeal to ‘science’ and alternative methods were considered inferior at best and unacceptable at worst. Danziger began his career as a psychologist shortly after the Second World War when these methodological prescriptions, and the intolerance of any alterna- tives to them, were at their height. With the sole exception of his early work with laboratory rats, Danziger had never felt bound by these strictures. His work with children used what has been called the ‘clinical’ method of Piaget and his work in the sociology of knowledge in South Africa had used non-traditional methods as well. He had always been critical of the primacy of method in mainstream psy- chology and sometimes used the term, ‘methodolatry’ to describe this situation. A useful introduction to Danziger’s views on methodology is an article in Phi- losophy of the Social Sciences , with the title, “The methodological imperative in psychology” (Danziger, 1985b). However, when Danziger began to make psychological methodology the main focus of his historical research, his criticisms moved to a different level. This change crystallized around 1983 and eventually resulted in Danziger’s best-known work. Constructing the Subject: Historical Origins of Psychological Research (Danziger, 1990). It is virtually impossible to summarize such a rich work in a few paragraphs but some of its most salient points will be briefly mentioned. For Danziger, the psychology experiment using human participants constitutes a social situation exemplifying various social regularities. He contrasts the situation in the early German experimental research of Wundt and others where the participant was described as a ‘research participant’ or ‘observer’ , rather than a ‘subject’ . The role of the participant was at least as important as that of the experimenter, as may be seen from the fact that these roles were often interchangeable. In some cases, the role of the ‘observer’ was more important than that of the ‘experimenter’ and this situation is reflected in the fact that the former was sometimes a person of greater social status than the latter. An example of this occurs in the famous experiments of the Wurzburg School in which the head of the institute, Kiilpe often acted as the ‘observer’ in the experiments of someone like Biihler, who was officially his assistant (Biihler, 1907; 1908). It could even happen that an experimental report was published not by the experimenter but by the ‘observer’ ; something that would be unthinkable in standard modern research. The term for the research participant that eventually came to be adopted in standard experimental research, ‘subject’ is not to be found in any of this early experimental work. It had previously been used in medical work on hypnotism and reflects the unequal division of power that occurs in the hypnotic situation. Thus the adoption of this term by experimental psychologists reflects a change in the division of power between the researcher and the participant. Throughout this work, Danziger shows that the way of doing experiments that subsequently became enshrined as the only valid way of doing an experiment is merely one of several possible alternatives. He also shows that psychology has 6 ADRIAN C. BROCK always used a variety of investigative practices, of which experiments are only one, and can trace its history not only to Wundt’s laboratory but also to the clinical work of Charcot in France and the psychological testing that was done by Gabon in England. The history of these investigative practices indicates a gradual narrowing of research possibilities over the years. Moreover, the methods that eventually came to be adopted were adopted mainly for extraneous reasons and not on strictly scientific grounds. Using the phrase, ‘marketable methods’, Danziger shows how psychologists adopted methods that would yield results that would be of interest to the social institutions that had an interest in prediction and control. Danziger’s work has its parallels in recent work in the interdisciplinary area of ‘science studies’ that encompasses history, philosophy, sociology, and even anthropology, of science. Much of this work implies a critique of the quasi-religious status that science has acquired in some quarters and examines it as a social product. While some historians, philosophers and sociologists in the field of science studies have a broader agenda, Danziger is more concerned with psychology itself. If the accepted methods of mainstream psychology lose their quasi-religious status, then they too can be open to debate and the possibility of alternatives can be discussed. This difference in emphasis seems to be acknowledged when Danziger says that his approach owes much to the field of science studies but suggests that he may “have produced a different kind of insider’s history” (Danziger, 1990; p. vii). Even before Constructing the Subject had appeared, there was a noticeable shift in Danziger’s interests towards what he originally called ‘the history of psy- chological concepts and categories’ and later called ‘the history of psychological objects’. Danziger first became interested in this topic when he was a visiting pro- fessor at Gadjah Mada University in Jogjakarta, Indonesia from 1957 to 1959. He went there as an employee of the Indonesian government with the specific man- date to introduce ‘western’ psychology to the curriculum. To his surprise, he found that he had an Indonesian colleague who was teaching a local form of psychology called, ‘ilmu djiwa' that was based on Hindu philosophy. Danziger suggested that they conduct joint seminars in which the local and the ‘western’ views of psychol- ogy could be compared but the joint seminars never took place because they could not find a common set of ‘objects’ around which the seminars could be based. The local psychology had no equivalents for the basic objects of English-language psychology, such as ‘motivation’, ‘intelligence’, ‘personality’ etc., and there were no equivalents in English-language psychology for the objects that were central to the local psychology. This seemed to be clear evidence that psychological objects were social products (Danziger, 1997a; see also Brock, 1995a; 1995b). Many other examples of this phenomenon could be given. A topic that has been explored in some detail is the Japanese emotion of ‘amae’. This emotion is very important in Japanese culture and many popular Japanese songs are based on it. There is no equivalent in English, or indeed in any other European language, for this emotion and it seems to be a specifically Japanese way of feeling (Morsbach INTRODUCTION 7 and Tylor, 1976). It is, of course, possible for non-Japanese persons to gain some understanding of what the emotion is about but it would take several paragraphs to explain it rather than one word. The insight that these concepts, categories or objects — whatever term is preferred — are social products leads to the obvious con- clusion that they have a history as well. Harre (1983) has pointed to the existence of the now obsolete emotion of 'accidae’ which was important in medieval Europe and which was manifested by a neglect of one’s religious duties. Neglecting one’s religious duties is less important to modern Europeans and this may explain why the emotion is now obsolete. Danziger has focussed not on psychological objects that are now obsolete but on the historical origins of the some of the most com- mon objects of research in American psychology. In doing so, he has continued the process that he began in Constructing the Subject of historicizing aspects of psychology that are usually regarded as fixed and eternal. If the methods of psy- chology are viewed as sacred and not as social products that have a history, then this is even more true of the basic objects of psychological research. Perhaps the first point that needs to be addressed is what exactly a ‘psycholog- ical object’ is in Danziger’s view. A key text in this regard is an article that Danziger published in Annals of Theoretical Psychology in 1993 under the title, “Psycho- logical objects, practice, and history” (Danziger, 1993a). In this work, Danziger defines psychological objects in social terms: “They are simply the things that psy- chologists take to be their proper objects of investigation or professional practice” (p. 24). It therefore follows that psychological objects vary from place to place and in different historical periods. One psychological object that Danziger has not examined but which can serve as an example of this phenomenon is ‘stress’. This is now regarded as a major social problem in most developed countries and it is the object of a great deal of psychological research. However, until the middle of the twentieth century, the word had a purely physical meaning and referred to a force being exerted on a physical object. It has retained this meaning in terms such as ‘stress fracture’. It was only after this term was applied metaphorically to human psychology around the middle of the twentieth century that it came to be regarded as a suitable object of psychological research (e.g. Selye, 1978). Thus ‘stress’ became a psychological object after this period, whereas previously it was not. Danziger’s main work on the history of psychological objects is his book. Naming the Mind: How Psychology Found Its Language (Danziger, 1997a). In this work, Danziger outlines the historical origins of several common objects of research in American psychology: behavior, learning, emotion, motivation, atti- tude, intelligence and personality. These are the kind of topics that might form the headings of the chapters in an American introductory text. Perhaps the most surprising result of this research is how ‘modern’ many of these concepts are. They are not much older than psychology itself. Although Danziger has tended to focus on psychological objects that were ultimately successful, he acknowledges that there have been failures as well. An example might be the ‘BewuBtseinslagen’ of ADRIAN C. BROCK the Wurzburg School, which have been mistranslated as 'imageless thought’ but are more appropriately characterized as ‘states of consciousness’. Towards the end of the book, Danziger suggests that the psychological objects that are currently popular in American psychology will eventually fall out of favor and be replaced by others. In spite of there being a literature on the history of scientific objects by historians of science (e.g. Canguilhem, 1955; Smith, 1991, Daston, 2000), there has been virtually no work on the history of psychological objects by psychologists. This may be the outcome of what Danziger calls ‘naive naturalism’. This is the view that the current objects of English-language psychology correspond to some natural division of reality and can thus be regarded as ‘natural kinds’. In place of this view, Danziger has adopted the term, ‘human kinds’ from his colleague in Toronto, Ian Hacking (e.g. Hacking, 1995; see also Danziger, 1999). An important characteristic of human kinds is that they not only help us to understand and to explain human action. They influence the action as well. It is probably of no importance to a dolphin whether we characterize it as a ‘mammal’ or a ‘fish’ but it is of great importance to parents who physically punish their children whether we characterize their actions as ‘discipline’ or ‘child abuse’. One of the features of a human kind is that its application can sometimes be controversial. The person to whom it is applied can passively accept it or vigorously reject it. What both Hacking and Danziger want to emphasize here is the oft-stated view that human beings are ‘self-defining creatures’. It is because of this that the activities of psychologists differ from those of their counterparts in the natural sciences since they are not merely attempting to describe a human nature that exists independently of the descriptions that they use. Their descriptions help to shape the phenomenon under investigation and it is here that the relationship between psychological objects and social practices lies. Danziger has sometimes been mistakenly characterized as a ‘sociological reductionist’ for holding these views (Stam, this volume). While he clearly wishes to demonstrate that knowledge has a sociological dimension, he makes no claim to knowing what the ultimate nature of psychological knowledge is. The issue is seen as an empirical question that has yet to be resolved: Our only hope of establishing the reach of psychological knowledge is not to take its universality for granted at the outset, but to treat each of its products as a histori- cally embedded achievement. Only when we understand something of this historical embeddedness of specific psychological objects and practices are we in a position to formulate intelligent questions about their possible transcendence. (Danziger, 1993a; p. 45) Elsewhere, Danziger (1993b) suggests that trying to decide on these issues in advance of carrying out any historical or cross-cultural research is like trying to judge the outcome of a court case before the evidence has been produced. He has INTRODUCTION 9 also written positively of the critical realism of Roy Bhaskar (Danziger, 1990; see also Bhaskar, 1978; 1979). According to Richards (2002b), this philosophy “attempts to recoup the implications of social constructionism by accepting that the objects of knowledge are objectively real, but conceding that the terms in which they are known or knowable are in some sense socially determined” (p. 334). Thus the sociology of knowledge and philosophical realism are not incompatible, as is often supposed. The history of psychological objects as an area of historical research is compatible with a wide range of philosophical views and Danziger’s realist position is only one possibility among several. However, it does need to be emphasized that when Danziger asserts that psychological objects are intimately related to the social practices of a particular time and place, he is referring to real social practices that have real effects on real people and not to some figment of our imagination. Danziger has continued this line of research with his most recent work on the history of memory. This was a topic that he initially considered for inclusion in Naming the Mind but he came to realise that it was so vast that it needed a separate treatment (Danziger, personal communication). This work marks an important departure from the psychological objects that were examined in Naming the Mind in one very important respect: the concept of ‘memory’ is not a recent creation but has existed in one form or another since at least the time of Plato. According to Danziger (2002), the appearance of this term is connected with the social practice of storing information in written form. Plato’s teacher, Socrates wrote nothing and relied on oral communication. It is no mere coincidence, therefore, that Plato introduced the concept with the metaphor of a wax tablet since it has always been linked to storing information in one form or another (see also Draaisma, 2000). The persistence of the concept can be explained in terms of the persistence of this social practice. Danziger also shows that there have been wildly different conceptions of the phenomenon over time and he has recently returned to the topic of Wundt in order to illustrate this point. It is well known that Wundt did not carry out any memory experiments in his Leipzig laboratory. The start of experimental research on this topic is usually traced to the work of Ebbinghaus in Berlin (Ebbinghaus, 1885). This situation is often explained in purely technical terms; that is, Wundt did not develop the appropriate experimental techniques. Underlying this assumption is the view of naive naturalism that memory has always been ‘out there’ and was merely waiting for someone to investigate it. According to Danziger (2001a), Wundt did not regard the topic of ‘memory’ as being of fundamental importance since, in his view, it was not one mental activity but the secondary product of several. It was a category of folk psychology — or what Wundt sometimes called, ‘vulgar psychology’ — and he dismissed it as an ‘empty name’; that is, a word that had no proper referent. Wundt was not the only person in nineteenth-century Germany who held these views and they would not have appeared strange to Wundt’s contemporaries. 10 ADRIAN C. BROCK Danziger has only published a small amount on this subject so far but it is already clear that he does not regard an apparently ‘transhistorical’ psychological object, such as memory, as being unaffected by socio-historical circumstances. THE CHAPTERS Some readers may be surprised by the use of ‘history’ and ‘theory’ throughout this introduction since these are sometimes seen as separate activities. This is par- ticularly true in the United States where the American Psychological Association has separate divisions for these activities. Divisions 26 (History of Psychology) and 24 (Theoretical/Philosophical Psychology ) respectively. This situation stands in sharp contrast to the institutional arrangements in the British and Canadian pro- fessional organizations, which have sections devoted to “History and Philosophy of Psychology”. Danziger is a philosophically minded historian of psychology who has been a frequent participant not only in the meetings of these two sections but also in the meetings of the International Society for Theoretical Psychology. He has also published his work in journals such as Theory and Psychology, Annals of Theoretical Psychology and even Philosophy of the Social Sciences (e.g. Danziger, 1985; 1993a; 1994). In an interview that I conducted with him in 1994, he expressed the view that history without theory cannot be good history and that theory without history cannot be good theory (Brock, 1995a; 1995b). He has recently returned to this topic in a book chapter titled, “Where history, theory and philosophy meet: The historiography of psychological objects” (Danziger, 2003). As may be evinced from the title of this chapter, Danziger’ s work exemplifies this unified approach to history, theory and philosophy. Although Danziger’ s philosophical interests are evident in his historical work, he prefers to use the term, ‘theory’; partly in order to distinguish it from that branch of philosophy called, ‘philosophy of mind’ or ‘philosophical psychology’ (Danziger, personal communication). While the authors in this volume may differ in their views on how ‘history’ and ‘theory’ might be related, they are all united in the view that these activities should not be treated as distinct. Two of the authors in this book were the editors of a special issue of Annals of Theoretical Psychology that was devoted to exploring this relationship and two others contributed articles to this special issue (van Rappard & van Strien, 1993; Danziger, 1993a; Staeuble, 1993). Hank Stam is well known for his contributions to both history and theory of psychology and as the editor of the journal. Theory and Psychology. He is therefore well qualified to discuss the theoretical implications of Danziger’s work. As mentioned in the previous section, one aspect of this work that has been the object of much discussion in theoretical circles is its epistemological implications. While Danziger rejects charges of ‘sociological reductionism’ and regards himself as a philosophical realist, some psychologists have the impression that ‘reality’ is being glossed over or left out of his account. In this chapter, Stam argues that such INTRODUCTION 11 charges are unwarranted and that Danziger’s epistemological views can be better understood if ‘history’ is taken as the departure point for these views rather than ‘psychology’ as it usually understood. The chapter by Johann Louw examines what is chronologically the earliest work. Danziger’s South African research exemplifying a sociology of knowledge approach provides some interesting links with his later historical work. As Louw points out, Danziger has continued to be a sociologically oriented historian of psy- chology and not just in his account of the ‘peripheral’ aspects of psychology, such as the history of psychologists and institutions. His sociological analysis extends to psychological knowledge itself and, although his work is generally characterized as ‘history and theory of psychology’, it can be seen as an exercise in the sociol- ogy of knowledge as well. Danziger’s work is sometimes identified with what has come to be known as “The social constructionist movement in modern psychol- ogy’’ (Gergen, 1985). However, his sociologically oriented history of psychology has its roots in the much older tradition of the sociology of knowledge. He has suggested that it is more appropriate to regard the area of ‘social construction’ as an interdisciplinary field and that placing the suffix ‘ism’ on the end of this term can only raise false expectations about the amount of agreement that exists between the researchers from a variety of disciplines who work in this area (Danziger, 1997b). Like Danziger, Andrew Winston has been working on the history of psy- chological methodology since the 1980s. They are also familiar with each other’s work and there may have been some mutual influence since their research has overlapped. One topic that both have examined is the introduction of the concept of ‘variable’ into psychology (e.g. Winston & Blais, 1996; Danziger & Dzinas, 1998). Far from being a timeless and universal feature of science, the term was adopted by American psychologists in the 1930s and subsequently exported to other parts of the world. Winston also shows quite clearly that the term is a part of the internal culture of psychology and is hardly used in physics and other natural sciences. This work on the ‘variable’ concept is a good example of how the history of psychological methodology and the history of psychological objects can over- lap. Winston also provides an account of a psychological object that died a very quick death: the ‘experimentee’. The term was proposed by Saul Rosenzweig in the 1930s but he decided to abandon it following pressure from E. G. Boring. What is particular interesting about this account is the importance that was placed on the homogeneity of the methodological terms that were used within the discipline. Pieter van Strien develops a different aspect of Constructing the Subject in his chapter on the single- subject research design. In his own work, Danziger had focussed on the historical origins of mainstream American research methods. One of the main features of these methods is that they take a large sample of ‘subjects’ and then work with the statistical averages from these results. This is equally true of experimental research that is interested in general human performance and in personality research where individual differences are the main focus of interest. Danziger described this situation as “the triumph of the aggregate” and 12 ADRIAN C. BROCK shows how the early German experimenters based their theories on evidence drawn from one participant or a small number of participants (Danziger, 1990). One of the most famous examples is Ebbinghaus who was both the subject and the experimenter in his memory research (Ebbinghaus, 1885). Danziger acknowledges that the single-subject research design has continued in psychophysics and van Strien expands these remarks. He also points out that the design has continued in other areas of psychology as well. Perhaps the best-known example is B. F. Skinner who frequently used a single animal in his research. Van Strien also refers to computer modelling, which belongs to a historical period that is later than the period that Danziger discusses in Constructing the Subject. The chapter provides an interesting extension of Danziger’s work to other investigative practices. Van Strien acknowledges that psychologists like Skinner who did single-subject research were out of step with the majority of American psychologists and it is the methods of this majority that were the focus of Danziger’s research. He also suggests that the persistence of the single-subject design can be explained in sociological terms. Richard Walsh-Bowers is a former student of Danziger whose work in recent years has centered on research ethics and the social aspects of the research situation. The latter is an important focus of Constructing the Subject where Danziger had drawn attention to the research relationship in the early German experiments, which was a relationship of equals and sometimes a relationship in which the research participant had greater social status than the experimenter. It was only later that research participants came to be described as ‘subjects’, who had to be naive and who were deliberately kept naive by using deception and other strategies. Walsh- Bowers’ aim is to introduce a greater degree of equality and democracy in the research situation and his chapter provides a good example of how critical history is often written with the aim of changing the present. Following the publication of Constructing the subject , Danziger addressed a broad set of themes related to the historiography of psychology. In 1992, he presented a paper at a meeting of Cheiron-Europe titled, “In praise of marginality” (Danziger, 1992b). The paper discussed several aspects of marginality but perhaps the most important was the problematic status of history and theory of psychology in relation to psychology. This theme is taken up by Betty Bayer in her discussion of the prospects of a cultural-historical approach to psychology. Her work also touches on a theme that Danziger (1994) addresses in his paper, “Does the history of psychology have a future?”. In this paper, Danziger suggested that it is important for critical historians to maintain a presence within psychology, and within science in general, so that they will be in a better position to have their views heard. Historians of science work in different departments from practising scientists, go to different conferences and publish in different forums. This is not an ideal position to be in if one wishes to influence the course of science. Bayer offers a somewhat depressing picture of scholars being hounded out of their academic disciplines and being forced to do their work elsewhere. Those who identify with critical INTRODUCTION 13 history will surely have different experiences in this regard but Bayer does end with an optimistic assessment of the prospect of change. Her chapter points to the importance of interdisciplinary work and interdisciplinary alliances. For those of us who take a sociological and historical perspective on these matters, disciplines are not ‘natural kinds’ that correspond to some natural division in the world but the product of social conventions that vary historically and cross-culturally. Even the label, ‘psychologist’ is a ‘human kind’ that one can accept or reject; or accept with qualifications. The inclusion of Hans van Rappard in this volume is an indication of the edi- tors’ intentions of producing a critical discussion of Danziger’s work. Van Rappard is well known as a critic of Danziger’s approach to the history of psychology (van Rappard, 1997; 1998). In this chapter, van Rappard discusses the work of Wundt, a topic that was central to Danziger’s early work in history and theory of psychology, and seeks to highlight what he considers to be the differences between the general approach of Danziger and that of his own. Van Rappard has criticised the trend among historians of psychology towards ‘critical’ history and he correctly views Danziger as one of the most prominent representatives of this approach. According to van Rappard, the most appropriate kind of work that a psychologist-historian (as opposed to a professional historian) can do is to examine the great theorists of the past in order to assist current theorizing and he offers his account of Wundt as an example of this approach. What complicates the situation considerably is that Danziger himself has used a similar approach in his discussions of Wundt’s Volkerpsychologie (Danziger, 1983) or Lewin’s early research in Berlin, which he has described as “buried treasure” (Danziger; 1990; p. 178). There is nothing inconsistent about being critical of mainstream psychology while simultaneously looking for alternatives among approaches to the subject that were historically less successful. Indeed, it could be argued that one is a necessary complement to the other in North America where to use the works of the past as a guide to the present is already a highly unorthodox step. While reading van Rappard’s critique of Danziger’s views on the history of psychology, and also that of Dehue (1998), it should be remembered that these Dutch authors work in a different social context from that of Danziger since this may explain some of the differences in their views. One example of these local differences is the different status of historical psy- chology in (continental) Europe and the English-speaking world (Brock, 1995a; 1995b). Historical psychology has been an important theme in Danziger’s re- cent work, though he was aware of its significance at an early stage (see Louw, this volume). This subject has long existed on the margins of English-language psychology (e.g. Barbu, 1960) but it is taken much more seriously in Germany (e.g. Loewenstein, 1992; Sonntag & Jiitteman, 1993) and in the Netherlands (e.g. Verhave & van Hoorn, 1984; Peeters, 1996). Willem van Hoorn is a former student of Jan Hendrik van den Berg, a psychiatrist who represents a distinctive phe- nomenological approach to historical psychology (van den Berg, 1961), and he 14 ADRIAN C. BROCK has been engaged with this field for many years. His chapter is a plea for the inclu- sion of historical psychology as an integral part of the historiography of scientific psychology through the phenomenological concept of the ‘life world’. Irmingard Staeuble has been a prominent figure in the recent work on histor- ical psychology in Germany (e.g. Staeuble, 1991; 1993). She is also well known as a critic of the postcolonial relationship between the so-called ‘first’ and ‘third’ worlds in psychology and has argued for a greater openness to non-western con- ceptions of knowledge. In this respect, her interests overlap with Danziger’s own. It was Danziger’s encounter with an alien form of psychological knowledge in Indonesia that led to his interest in the history of psychological objects. He has also criticized the unfortunate tendency to identify the history of American psy- chology with the history of psychology as a whole and has advocated what he calls a ‘polycentric’ approach to the field (Danziger, 1991; 1996). In this chapter, Staeuble outlines the expansion of western psychology around the world after the Second World War and the attempts to make it more appropriate to the local con- text under the label, ‘indigenization’ (e.g. Moghaddam, 1987). She also discusses the prospects of the kind of polycentric history of psychology that Danziger has outlined. The book ends with a chapter by Kurt Danziger himself. This chapter contains comments on the chapters by the other authors and also a discussion of some of the issues that these chapters raise. One topic that Danziger explores in some detail is the issue of ‘disciplinarity’ . Psychologists have traditionally identified their work with the natural sciences and neglected the subject’s links to the social sciences and humanities (Danziger, 1994; Brock, 1995a; 1995b). As Danziger points out, the situation is maintained by erecting barriers to subjects like sociology, anthropology, history and philosophy and one possible strategy for changing the situation is to move outside this disciplinary ghetto and to participate in interdisciplinary ventures. NOTE 1 I would like to thank Kurt Danziger and my co-editors, Johann Louw and Willem van Hoorn for their helpful comments on an earlier draft. REFERENCES Allport, G. W. (1985). The historical background of modern social psychology. In G. Lindzey and E. Aronson (Eds.), A handbook of social psychology, vol. I. (3rd ed.; pp. 1 46) Cambridge, MA: Addison- Wesley. [Original work published 1954.] Ash. M. G. (1983). The self-presentation of a discipline: History of psychology in the United States between pedagogy and scholarship. In L. Graham. P. Weingart and W. Lepenies (Eds.), Functions and uses of disciplinary histories, (pp. 143-189) Dordrecht: Riedel. INTRODUCTION 15 Barbu, Z. (1960). Problems of historical psychology. New York: Grove Press. Berg, J. H. van den (1961). The changing nature of man. New York: Norton. Bhaskar, R. (1978). A realist theory of science. Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press. Bhaskar, R. (1979). The possibility of naturalism. Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press. Boring, E. G. (1950). A history of experimental psychology. (2nd ed.) New York: Appleton-Century- Crofts. [Original work published 1929.] Boring, E. G. (1953). A history of introspection. Psychological Bulletin, 50, 169-189. Brock, A. (1993). Something old, something new: The ‘reappraisal’ of Wundt in history textbooks. Theory and Psychology, 3, 235-242. Brock, A. (1995a). An interview with Kurt Danziger. History and Philosophy of Psychology Bulletin, 7, 10-22. Brock, A. (1995b). Constructing the subject: An interview with Kurt Danziger. Psychologie en Maatschappij, 19, 351-366. Brock, A. (1998). Pedagogy and research. The Psychologist, 11, 169-171. Biihler, K. (1907). Tatsachen und Probleme zu einer Psychologie der Denkvorgange: 1 . Uber Gedanken. Archivfiir die gesamte Psychologie, 9, 297-365. Biihler, K. (1908). 2. Uber Gedankenzusammenhange; 3. Uber Gedankenerrinerungen. Archivfiir die gesamte Psychologie, 12, 1-92. Biihler, K. (1965). Die Krise der Psychologie. (3rd ed.) Stuttgart: Gustav Fischer. [Originally published 1927.] Canguilhem, G. (1955). La formation de concept du reflexe aux 17e et 18e siecles. Paris: Presses Universitaire de France. Danziger, K. (1953). The interaction of hunger and thirst in the rat. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 5, 10-21. Danziger, K. (1958). Children’s earliest conceptions of economic relationships. Journal of Social Psychology, 47, 231-240. Danziger, K. (1963). Ideology and utopia in South Africa: A methodological contribution to the soci- ology of knowledge. British Journal of Sociology, 14, 59-76. Danziger, K. (1971). Socialization. Harmondsworth: Penguin. Danziger, K. (1976). Interpersonal communication. New York: Pergamon. Danziger, K. (1979a). The positivist repudiation of Wundt. Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, 15, 205-230. Danziger, K. (1979b). The social origins of modem psychology. In A. R. Buss (Ed.), Psychology in social context (pp. 27^4-5). New York: Irvington. Danziger, K. ( 1980a). The history of introspection reconsidered. Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, 16, 241-262. Danziger, K. (1980b). Wundt and the two traditions in psychology. In R. W. Rieber (Ed.), Wilhelm Wundt and the making of a scientific psychology (pp. 73-87). New York: Plenum. Danziger, K. (1980c). Wundt’s theory of behavior and volition. In R. W. Rieber (Ed.), Wilhelm Wundt and the making of a scientific psychology (pp. 89-1 15). New York: Plenum. Danziger, K. (1980d). On the threshold of the new psychology: Situating Wundt and James. In W. G. Bringmann & R. D. Tweney (Eds.), Wundt studies (pp. 363-379). Toronto: Hogrefe. Danziger, K. (1980e). Wundt’s psychological experiment in the light of his philosophy of science. Psychological Research, 42, 109-122. Danziger, K. (1983). Origins and basic principles of Wundt’s Volkerpsychologie. British Journal of Social Psychology, 22, 303-313. Danziger, K. (1984). Towards a conceptual framework for a critical history of psychology. In H. Carpintero & J. Peiro (Eds.), Essays in honor of J. Brozek (pp. 99-107). Valencia: Monograffas Rev. Hist. Psicologfa. Danziger, K. (1985a). The origins of the psychological experiment as a social institution. American Psychologist, 40, 133-140. 16 ADRIAN C. BROCK Danziger, K. (1985b). The methodological imperative in psychology. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 15, 1-13. Danziger, K. (1988). Wilhelm Wundt and the emergence of experimental psychology. In G. N. Cantor, J. R. R. Christie, & R. C. Olby (Eds.), A companion to the history of modern science (pp. 906^109). Chicago: Chicago University Press. Danziger, K. ( 1 990). Constructing the subject: Historical origins of psychological research. Cambridge/ New York: Cambridge University Press. Danziger (1991). Guest editor’s introduction. History of the Human Sciences, 4, 327-333. Danziger, K. (1992a). Ideas and constructions: Reply to reviewers. Theory and Psychology, 2, 255-256. Danziger, K. (1992b). In praise of marginality. Paper presented at the Annual meeting of Cheiron- Europe, Groningen, Netherlands. Danziger, K. (1993a). Psychological objects, practice, and history. Annals of Theoretical Psychology, 8, 15^17. Danziger, K. (1993b). History, practice and psychological objects: Reply to commentators. Annals of Theoretical Psychology, 8, 71-84. Danziger, K. (1994). Does the history of psychology have a future? Theory and Psychology, 4, 467^4-84. Danziger, K. (1996). Towards a polycentric history of psychology. Paper presented at the 26th Inter- national Congress of Psychology in Montreal. Danziger, K. (1997a). Naming the mind: How psychology found its language. London: Sage. Danziger, K. (1997b). Essay review: The varieties of social construction. Theory and Psychology, 7, 399—416. Danziger, K. (1999). Natural kinds, human kinds and historicity. In W. Maiers, B. Bayer, B. Duarte Esgalhado, R. Joma & E. Schraube (Eds.), Challenges to theoretical psychology (pp. 78-83). Toronto: Captus Press. Danziger, K. (2001a). Sealing off the discipline: Wundt and the psychology of memory. In C. D. Green, M. Shore & T. Teo (Eds.), Psychological thought in the nineteenth century: The transition from philosophy to science and the challenges of uncertainty (pp. 45-62). Washington: American Psychological Association. Danziger, K. (2001b). Whither the golden oldies of ESHHS: The historiography of psychological objects. Address at the 20th annual meeting of the European Society for History of the Human Sciences, Amsterdam. Danziger, K. (2002). How old is psychology, particularly concepts of memory? History and Philosophy of Psychology, 4, 1-12. Danziger, K. (2003). Where history, theory and philosophy meet: The biography of psychological objects. In D. B. Hill & M. J. Krai (Eds.), About psychology: Essays at the crossroads of history, theory and philosophy, (pp. 19-33). New York: SUNY Press. Danziger, K. & Dzinas, K. (1997). How psychology got its variables. Canadian Psychology, 38, 43-48. Daston, L. (Ed.) (2000). Biographies of scientific objects. Chicago/London: University of Chicago Press. Dehue, T. (1998). Community historians and the dilemma of rigor vs. relevance: A comment on Danziger and Van Rappard. Theory and Psychology, 8, 653-661. Draaisma, D. (2000). Metaphors of memory: A history of ideas about the mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Originally published in Dutch in 1995.] Driesch, H. (1926). Grundprobleme der Psychologie: Ihre Krisis in der Gegenwart. Leipzig: Reinicke. Ebbinghaus, H. (1885). Uberdas Geddchtnis. Leipzig: Duncker und Humblot. Gergen, K. ( 1 985). The social constructionist movement in modem psychology. American Psychologist, 40, 266-275. Hacking, I. (1995). The looping effects of human kinds. In D. Sperber, D. Premack & A. J. Premack (Eds.), Causal cognition: A multi-disciplinary approach (pp. 351-383). Oxford: Clarendon Press. INTRODUCTION 17 Harre, R. (1983). Personal being: A theory for individual psychology. Oxford: Blackwell. Heidbreder, E. (1933). Seven psychologies. New York: Century. Loewenstein, B. (Ed.) (1992). Geschichte und Psychologie: Anndherungsversuche. Pfaffenweiler: Centaurus. Mannheim, K. (1936). Ideology and utopia: An introduction to the sociology of knowledge. London: Routledge. Moghaddam, F. M. (1987). Psychology in the three worlds as reflected by the crisis in social psychology and the move toward indigenous third-world psychology. American Psychologist, 42, 912-920. Morsbach, H. & Tylor, W. J. (1976). Some Japanese- Western linguistic differences concerning dependency need: The case of amae. In R. Harre (Ed.), Life sentences: Aspects of the social role of language. New York: Wiley. Nelson, R. D. (1992). The analysis of styles of thought. British Journal of Sociology, 43, 25-54. Peeters, H. (1996). Psychology: The historical dimension. Tilburg: Syntax. Richards, G. (2002a). History of psychology: The discipline of the future. History and Philosophy of Psychology, 4, 13-22. Richards, G. (2002b). Putting psychology in its place: A critical historical overview. (2nd ed.) London: Routledge. Selye, H. (1978). The stress of life. New York: McGraw-Hill. Smith, R. (1992). Inhibition: History and meaning in the sciences of mind and brain. Berkeley/Los Angeles: University of California Press. Sonntag, M. & Jiitteman, G. (Eds.) (1993). Individuum und Geschichte: Beitrage zur Diskussion um eine “Historische Psychologie”. Heidelberg: Asanger. Staeuble, I. (1991). ‘Psychological man’ and human subjectivity in historical perspective. History of the Human Sciences, 4, 417-^-32. Staeuble, I. (1993). History and the psychological imagination. Annals of Theoretical Psychology, 8, 85-117. Van Rappard, J. F. H. & van Strien, P. J. (1993). History ands theory: Introduction. Annals of Theoretical Psychology, 8, 1-14. Van Rappard, J. F. H. (1997). History of psychology turned inside(r) out: A comment on Danziger. Theory and Psychology, 7, 101-105. Van Rappard, J. F. H. (1998). Towards household history: A reply to Dehue. Theory and Psychology, 8, 663-667. Verhave, T. & van Hoorn, W. (1984). The temporalization of the self. In K. J. Gergen and M. M. Gergen (Eds.), Historical social psychology (pp. 325-345). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Vygotsky, L. [Wygotski, L.] (1985). Die Krise der Psychologie in ihrer historischen Bedeutung. In Ausgewdhlte Schriften I (pp. 57-277). Berlin: Volk und Wissen. [Written in Russian in 1926 and originally published in this language in 1982.] Winston, A. S. & Blais, D. J. (1996). What counts as an experiment: A transdisciplinary analysis of textbooks, 1930-1970. American Journal of Psychology, 109, 599-616. Woodworth, R. S. (1931). Contemporary schools of psychology. New York: Ronald Press. Chapter 1 RECONSTRUCTING THE SUBJECT KURT DANZIGER AND THE REVISIONIST PROJECT IN HISTORIOGRAPHIES OF PSYCHOLOGY 1 Henderikus J. Stam The greatest obstacles to good scholarship are to be found in the ‘god tricks’ that serve to hide and obscure the necessary partiality involved in knowledge production. Kurt Danziger (1998) INTRODUCTION It is both a pleasure and a privilege to contribute to this volume of scholars honoring the work of Professor Kurt Danziger. His influence is deeply felt by all of us who have attempted to understand the history of the discipline of psychology as more than a mere accumulation of ideas and empirical results and he has inspired the critical work of those who have attempted to change the mainstream of that discipline by showing us that investigative practices are deeply carved out of taken for granted worlds. I would like here especially to consider the relationship between Danziger’s work and questions of theory. This is a tall order indeed so I intend to engage only a modest aspect of that topic here, namely the epistemological implications for psychological theory embedded in the historical work conducted by Danziger. The continuous interplay between our theoretical discourse and investigative practices and the embeddedness of those practices in social contexts not of our own making makes psychological theory the outcome of more than the ideas of individual 19 20 H. J. ST AM scientists. Addressing this topic should be relatively effortless given that Danziger has himself addressed the implications of his work in both of his major historical books. Constructing the Subject (1990a) and Naming the Mind (1997a) as well as in numerous other papers (e.g., Danziger, 1990b, 1993a, 1994). On the other hand, having addressed the issue he has also shown that it is not a simple matter of drawing out a few implications from his work but that on his own account history and theory are clearly not independent activities. In this sense Danziger can be counted among those who, like others such as Michel Foucault, have challenged the prevailing ethos of the human sciences and argued that from the vantage of history there is so much more at stake in these sciences than was at first supposed. By way of introducing the narrative, the point of my paper is perhaps best captured by the following anecdote: While attending a conference in 1 989 at which Danziger gave a talk in which he outlined some of his key notions in the history of psychology prior to the publication of Constructing the Subject (Danziger, 1990a), I was seated beside a senior psychologist. During the ensuing discussion, which consisted mainly of a rather predictable debate on the distinction between intellectual and contextual history, Danziger held his ground without allowing himself to be drawn into the more exaggerated and heated aspects of the contest. My senior colleague turned to me and pronounced that he wished Danziger would take a stronger stand because “we need our historians to provide us with a vision.” Presumably my colleague meant a vision of what the discipline could be in the light of the kind of critical history Danziger has written. In retrospect however I do believe that there is a vision in the work of Kurt Danziger, and it is that vision that I would like to place on the table. For in elaborating this particular aspect of Danziger’s work we will come closer to addressing the question of history and its relationship to theory. THEORY Theory, from the Greek Oecopia and Latin theoria meant, among other things, contemplation or observation. This meaning has lingered in the modern English usage of the term; as late as 1710 John Norris could say that “speculative knowledge contemplates truth for itself, and accordingly stops and rests in the contemplation of it, which is what we commonly call theory” (as cited in the OED). At the same time of course we see the gradual adoption of the term within the sciences and its strict application by Newton to mean “invariant relations among terms designating manifest qualities” (Losee, 1980, p. 91). He divided this meaning strictly from his views on ‘hypotheses’ which are statements about terms for which no measuring procedures are known (hence Newton’s famous dictum, “Hypotheses non lingo”). This view was modified over a period of 300 years up to the logical empiricists of the twentieth century who claimed that theories must be deductive systems in RECONSTRUCTING THE SUBJECT 21 which laws are theorems. The spectacular demise of the logical empiricist system in the space of forty years has been widely described and analyzed and I will not pursue this here. In short, it is the failure (or impossibility) of maintaining the key distinction between a theoretical language and observational terms that created such difficulties both for logical empiricists and for those who would formalize theory in science more generally. Theory in the human sciences, and in psychology in particular, never ap- proximated the grand schemes articulated by luminaries of the logical empiricist movement such as Hempel and Carnap. Nonetheless, the latter provided a kind of framework outside the discipline that could be called on at auspicious moments for defense. Logical empiricism worked as a kind of Non-proliferation Treaty for theory, where theory could be contained so long as it was held to be, in principle, a species of deductive system. However the notion that observations were dependent on, continually infected by, or otherwise structured by theoretical considerations (e.g., Hanson, 1958; Kuhn, 1970) opened up the question of theory in the philos- ophy of science more generally and eventually did so in psychology (e.g., Stam, 1996). The obverse is frequently left unsaid, namely that theory is deeply depen- dent on some presumed observational regularities of life itself, even in its most post-positivist moments. That is, theorizing and observing are not different kinds of activities so much as they are different forms of a similar activity of sense- making that varies in its systematicity, practical arrangements and consequences (Stam, 2000). In this the writing of history is not different in so far as it requires the adjudication of evidence always within a framework of prejudices and preconcep- tions, theoretical predilections and considerations of what audience one expects to address. HISTORY OF PSYCHOLOGY How do these considerations inform a discussion of the historical work of Kurt Danziger? Historiography is obviously deeply dependent on some presuppositions and pretexts that allow the enterprise to establish its legitimacy. The difficulties of the philosophy of history notwithstanding, the peculiar nature of disciplinary history only compounds such difficulties. For not only are we confronted with the question of what constitutes proper historical inquiry or ‘explanation’ but also with what constitutes the discipline in question, in Danziger’s case, psychology. These are not trivial problems, for while we may have agreement on how to proceed in writing a history of psychology we may not agree on what ought to constitute psychology, or vice versa. Fortunately, it turns out that these questions are related so that the answer to one is at least affected if not inspired by one’s answer to the second. This relationship exists on several levels: First, any historical undertaking is concerned with the activities, artifacts, expressions and desires of human beings 22 H. J. STAM and human collectives. Such conceptions of human nature that the historian has, and that are predominant in the discipline and culture of the historian, must obviously influence the work at hand, or on some accounts of history, make the work possible in the first instance. Second, the disciplinary history of psychology is also, in part, a history of the activities and artifacts of human beings, namely psychologists. Hence, the historian of psychology is first of all a historian, piecing together a narrative or account of places, persons, desires, contexts and ideas. Nevertheless, if our conception of human persons is like that of the mainstream of the discipline, that is, largely scientistic, individualistic and functional, then our history will focus on the development of disciplinary achievements and not on the institutional, political, social or even depth-psychological forces involved in creating such a model of human being in the first place. Or, if it is our primary goal to tell a story of the rise and development of aspects of the discipline proper, it is likely that we will remain confined to a disciplinary trajectory. To illustrate, I want briefly to examine critical history’s perennial foil, Edwin Boring. 2 The first sentences of the 1929 edition of his text are, The history of psychology is inextricably bound up with the history of philosophy, whereas the rise and development of experimental psychology is explicitly a phase of the history of scientific endeavor, (p. 3) As Boring himself noted later in his memoirs, he wrote his history of psychology out of a conception of history as progress. He noted that . . History is an ever- flowing stream through the centuries, a stream of events that occur in the nervous systems of persons situated so that their thoughts and acts become links in the course of progress” (Boring, 1961, p. 49). Such presentist history has long been criticized and the obvious variants still available today in the form of some under- graduate text books only speak to the lasting importance of such historiography to a discipline without a center, still uncertain about its scientific and institutional status. As soon as notions such as “progress” and the very history of science itself become contested, however, then the writing of such a disciplinary history becomes a matter for revision. And it is here that I would place Professor Danziger among the foremost practitioners of this revisionist history in psychology. Inspired by new histories of science and the social studies of science, it was possible to confront the seemingly ironclad notion of the division between an internal reconstruction of science and its external reconstruction. The theories of scientists are generated in the activities of scientists that are conducted in social institutions that have at least some of the characteristics of other, non-scientific social institutions. Knowing the historical location and specificity of our activities ought to be, on this account, a normal part of the understanding of generating theory and research. Indeed, both the understanding of the history of a problem and the construc- tion of its theory are, on this account, not radically different activities. Among RECONSTRUCTING THE SUBJECT 23 other things, history makes it possible to ask what the relationship is between one’s interest as a scientist, one’s membership in a particular local community and one’s accounts of one’s scientific activities. For example, the relationship between ideas of intelligence and intellect, the institutionalization and universalization of education, and the grading of human abilities all played a role in the develop- ment of the intelligence test in a manner that complicates any story of heroic pioneers who developed such tests (e.g., Danziger, 1997a). The post-war insti- tutionalization of North American experimental social psychology can hardly be conceived along the lines of brilliant individuals applying a new technology to a whole new field of human experience using selected insights garnered from Kurt Lewin. Instead, a complex relationship exists between ambitious post-war psy- chologists (who largely came from working-class urban environments), the need to demarcate social psychology from other fields of endeavor inside and outside psychology, and the recognition that only a psychology based on individuals would ever survive as social psychology inside the discipline. Along with more idiosyn- cratic contributions of the individuals involved, this provides a more coherent and context-sensitive account of the development (and failures) of contemporary social psychology (e.g., Stam, Lubek & Radtke, 2000). The point is not that the history of intellectual endeavors is complex but that the history of such endeavors are always unfolding and open to further contextualization and elaboration and can never just be accounts of intellectual achievements. As an aside, note that the focus on the formative activities of scientists in laboratories and their relation to theory are also a consequence of the under- determination of theories by data. That is, in the absence of genuine epistemolog- ical authority, most notably within the human sciences (see e.g., Weimer, 1979), scientists must retreat to sophistication and commitment as well as traditions of investigation. But such a retreat is negligible if the practical activities of one’s scientific activities are determined to be progressive by the community of science or one is able to demonstrate technological achievements to the world at large. In the absence of both, the activities of psychologists are important not only for what they reveal of the construction of a discipline but for what they hide. That is, psychological theories both permit and pretermit, precisely what a historical re- counting of the activities of psychologists ought to open up to view. History makes visible not just the obvious but the hidden interrelated processes of constructing and then separating data and theory out of a world of artifacts. In Constructing the Subject (1990a) Danziger demonstrates how a treatment of the investigative practices of the discipline radically shifts the emphasis of disciplinary history. Rather than tracking a unitary conception of the discipline, the question of investigative practices makes clear how psychology became a hybrid of various technologies of investigation. Together with a division of labor in the laboratory, the careful development of markets for its knowledge and the incorporation of statistical devices into its methods and manner of theorizing in the 24 H. J. STAM aggregate, psychology’s history no longer resembled the kind of linear, incremental enterprise we had come to expect from histories of psychology. In a later paper Danziger (1993a) extends this analysis to the “historicity of psychological objects” or the very things to which our theories refer. Here he reminds us that our objects of investigation are constructed, that is, they are the product of human activities, they have definitive uses, and they have a reference that itself needs to be explicated. This paper on the historicity of psychological objects seems to me a transitional one, pointing to a need for further analysis that was left open by the use of the term “objects.” The latter have the status of kinds of ‘hybrid’ entities (or quasi- objects, cf. Latour, 1993) that are at once natural and social, material and discursive. Latour’s claim is that distinctions between ‘constructed’ and ‘material’ accounts are misguided, all of our research objects have the character of both material and discursive, socially mediated properties. The construction and proliferation of such hybrids is not just the outcome of an investigative practice but includes the reformulation of powerful linguistic resources as well. It seems that this problem is addressed in Naming the Mind (1997a). In this volume the project is extended to the level of concept and terminology (rather than investigative practices or their objects). Indeed, by not just focusing on theory or strictly formal expositions, Danziger is able to keep from lapsing into old debates on the nature of psychological categories. Instead he argues that the very act of categorization in psychology displays a naive naturalism whereby natural kinds are presumed to exist in the categories that make up the theories of psychology. Yet by the time these theories are articulated in a formal sense, the act of naming and pointing to the appropriate object of investigation has already smuggled in a host of presuppositions and assumptions. Terms such as intelligence, emotion, motivation and the like are neither neutral nor natural but carry histories of conceptualization and use that deeply influence the possibilities open to the psychological theory that uses the concept. As Danziger notes, some of our most important terms are scientized and institutionalized variants of an eighteenth-century moral language. Naming the Mind completes the earlier study of the investigative practices of psychologists in Constructing the Subject by combining this work with a categor- ical and discursive study. Danziger’ s argument shifts from the crucial role played by investigative practices to the language guiding and in turn produced by those practices. As I will discuss below, this shift is important for the way Danziger has come to see the shaping of the discipline and the importance that a psychological discourse has above and beyond the research practices of its members. In short, Danziger argues that psychology established itself institutionally through astutely combining universal biological meanings with local social meanings that were mediated by the development of specific technologies. Certain investigative prac- tices, certain methods of psychological research and assessment — intelligence and personality testing, techniques for measuring the strength of attitudes and motives, standard learning situations, and so on — provided the basis for constituting classes RECONSTRUCTING THE SUBJECT 25 of scientifically validated phenomena that could be produced in a variety of prac- tical settings. In the course of time, the role of such technologies in establishing the meaning of psychological categories became ever more decisive. At this point we have come full circle, for the investigative practices are implicated in, and part of the discursive structure of the discipline. To return to my earlier formulation, it is here that theorizing and observing are indeed activities that are not separate but in their mutual organization and maintenance come to constitute disciplinary practices and findings. To stay with the visual trope, both observing and theorizing are attempts to make visible that which is conceived of as invisible and to render invisible or subsidiary other, competing accounts of the subject matter. The creation of objects of investigation and the findings related to those objects are rhetorical accomplishments as well as moments of invention. It is not only the language of psychology that is changed and shaped by the constitution of these objects but it is practices that are made possible by the objects in their creation. Narrating history in this manner leaves open a question that Danziger himself has worried about in his work across the span of two decades, namely, what are the implications for the current enterprise of psychology, or as he asked in Constructing the Subject , “when allowance is made for the factors that led to a relativizing of psychological knowledge, is there no remainder?” (p. 192). I will return here to an earlier worry that I noted in my review of Constructing the Subject (Stam, 1992), but with an intervening decade to consider the problem I would like to take a slightly different approach to this question. I was originally concerned that in that book, Danziger had backed out of the implications of his own analysis by noting that psychological realities could not be entirely accounted for by the limits of their investigative contexts and remained hidden under a veil of socially constituted practices. Like some of Danziger’s critics (e.g.. Ash, 1993; Mills, 1993) there is a continuing worry that something is being glossed or overlooked and that that something in fact consists of the core phenomena of the discipline. Danziger’s answer to this was initially to call on a form of critical realism as a solution (Bhaskar, 1978). The domain of the real was distinguished from the domain of the actual, on Bhaskar’s account, and the possibility was held up that there are determinant psychic mechanisms responsible for, or underlying, the ob- served regularities constituted through the investigative practices of psychologists. However, Danziger himself has moderated these claims on the realist-relativist question in his further work. For example, in his 1993 paper Danziger argues that psychology’s objects are not natural kinds and that methods are not theoretically and ethically neutral. Instead, argues Danziger, theories ought to be evaluated on criteria of practical consequences and reflexivity. By the time of the publication of Naming the Mind, this has retreated even further to the background. Here Danziger refers not to ‘objects’ but to the problematic relationship between discursive cate- gories and the phenomena themselves. Danziger clearly notes that the relationship 26 H. J. STAM here is constitutional, not representational, by which he means that a psychologi- cal object depends on “its human creator and the relationship between the object’s existence and its representation has become quite intimate” (p. 1 87). Relying on Ian Hacking’s notion of a ‘human kind’ as opposed to a ‘natural kind,’ Danziger notes that psychological objects aren’t just legends either. They have a circulation (in Hacking’s words [1994] they are subject to “looping effects”) in a cultural and human context and their circulation amends as well as reifies the phenomena in question. WHAT CAN HISTORY BE? Although his critics have accused him of, among other things, being a soci- ological reductionist (Mills, 1993) or of denigrating the possibilities of writing a history from the ‘inside’ of the discipline (Rappard, 1997) 3 , 1 think these critiques are off the mark (and Danziger has spoken eloquently for himself in reply, e.g., Danziger, 1993b, 1997b, 1998). I would like to place my comments in the context of broader debates in the philosophy of history. This is because the critiques of the work of historians such as Danziger are often couched in terms of the pernicious effects of relativism and explicitly or implicitly are aimed at propping up some conception of realism (e.g., Fox-Genovese & Lasch-Quinn, 1999). In his mature writings, it was R. G. Collingwood who recognized the mistake in this for the en- terprise of history. Often accused of skepticism himself by reviewers of The Idea of History (1946), Collingwood was careful not to become mired in this debate. For after all, in his earlier works such as Speculum Mentis (1924) he endorsed a realist program for history, if only implicitly, and by the time the Idea of History was published he had worked out precisely why he was not a realist. Skepticism, he argues, is a consequence of realism, “the discovery that the past as such is unknowable is the skepticism which is the permanent and necessary counterpart of the plain man’s realism” (1965, p. 100). It is the search for a factual past that is an illusion because the past as such can never be known again. Instead it led Collingwood away from “an unknowable past-in-itself ” to the activities of histo- rians themselves (Goldstein, 1970). Here Collingwood is often seen as relegating history to an act of imagination but this is too quick: In a paper on the historical imagination appended to the Idea of History he argues, . . . neither the raw material of historical knowledge, the detail of the here-and-now as given him in perception, nor the various endowments that serve him as aids to interpreting this evidence, can give the historian his criterion of historical truth. That criterion is the idea of history itself: the idea of an imaginary picture of the past. That idea is, in Cartesian language, innate; in Kantian language, a priori. It is not a chance product of psychological causes; it is an idea which every man possesses as part of the furniture of his mind, and discovers himself to possess in so far as he becomes conscious of what it is to have a mind. (1946, p. 248) RECONSTRUCTING THE SUBJECT 27 What keeps the “self-dependent, self-determining, and self-justifying” (p. 249) historical imagination from falling into skepticism is the discipline of history itself. Although Collingwood was not entirely clear about this, it is the structure of the discipline and what this discipline considers as good research practices, reliable evidence and the like that prevents the individual knower/historian from sliding off into the mere play of imagination. And Collingwood defended the notion of the autonomy of history precisely to preserve its status as a communal enterprise (Goldstein, 1970). 4 Collingwood saves history from the endless spiral of skepticism by an explicit turn to the imagination or the psychology of the individual historian. By extension, the community of historians makes history possible outside of any other authority. In this manner, Collingwood sees clearly that it is in its communal activities that historians decide history. This formulation predates the work of others who take up the problem of narrative, plot, and understanding, in particular Paul Ricoeur and Hayden White. The latter become preoccupied with a question of how language in its myriad forms makes the structure of story possible but when Ricoeur argues (against positivist textual objectivity) for a dialectic of understanding and explana- tion he means, in a manner reminiscent of Collingwood, that understanding is the ability to take up again, within the self, the work of structuring that is performed by the text. Explanation is always secondary to this understanding in that it consists in bringing to light the codes underlying the work of structuring. It is clear that understanding for Ricoeur is an imaginal act and explanation is made possible by the discourse available to us from our cultural understanding and presuppositions. History must be configured and brought into meaningful relation with other events in time, that is, made subject to emplotment. In the first volume of Time and Narrative Ricoeur (1984) attends to the ne- cessity of narrative (through configuration and emplotment) for a historical under- standing. Indeed, history must be configured, it must be brought into a meaningful relation with other events in time. Like Hayden White, Ricoeur argues that history is combined of the found and made-up, of the documented and the narrated. With- out configuration and emplotment there can be no history. Once narrated history is appropriated it is not only meaningful but it in turn becomes the ground for further configuration. Narratives extend the past into the present and make it possible to imagine a future (Ricoeur, 1988). Like Ricoeur, a range of historians of the twentieth-century has taken up the problem of the relation between the found and the made-up or the documented and the narrated. Hayden White (1973, 1978) too has argued that to produce a history, the chronicle must be converted to a meaningful narrative and hence must be emplotted. But the past has no plot and hence the historian provides an account, a narrative that emplots or encodes the traces or evidence. White is more formalist than Ricoeur (and other narrative historians), however, in so far as he argues that modes of emplotment are fundamentally dependent on tropes since there is no other entry into the rhetorical structure of language. Indeed, figurative characterizations 28 H. J. STAM are presupposed by the events to be represented and hence White’s claim that language operates tropologically to prefigure a field of perception. The boundary between the language that makes history and the content of that history remains always opaque. Despite White’s move into the formalism, so characteristic of later 20th cen- tury theorizing, he effectively supports Collingwood’s contention that history is an independent enterprise (even as he does not support Collingwood’s notion that history requires the reenactment of historical agents). All such theories of history are meant to prevent the encroachment of positivism and scientism on a historical consciousness. They embody the insights characteristic of the Geisteswisschen- schaften debates of the late 19th century where Dilthey already formulated the notion that lived experience is mediated through the imagination as well as the socio-cultural practices of the historical world (Makkreel, 1992; Mos, 1996). It was Ankersmit (2002) who recently argued that historical representation is a matter of the organization of the truth rather than the truth itself. Our representations may be “sensible, fruitful, helpful, thought-provoking (or not), but, while the data deployed may be true or false, the proposal deploying them cannot be” (p. 38). Hence the criteria are broadly aesthetic; there is no direct line back to the agents of history except through another point of view. But this point of view is not in the past but is embedded in the aesthetic language of the historian (Ankersmit, 1996). On this account history takes its force precisely from the need to represent the past in the absence of a fixed algorithmic manner of moving from the past to writing about that past (see also Stam, 2003). Attempts to retain for history its privileged capacity to judge the past are rare and today they exercise mostly those who see themselves as defenders of some version of ‘objectivity’ in the self-styled culture wars whose battles seem to be largely confined to university campuses in the United States (see Fox-Genovese & Lasch-Quinn, 1999). To return to Danziger’s work on psychology then, in the context of the larger debates in the philosophy of history Danziger’s work is not nearly as controversial or threatening as it appears to psychologists. But precisely because his audience has consisted largely of psychologists (and it would be a mistake not to write for psychologists), Danziger finds himself on the defensive for reasons that might seem odd to professional historians. Part of this is due to the role that histories of psychology have traditionally played in the discipline. Historical studies of psychology are first and foremost histories. Nonetheless, as Danziger has already pointed out on several occasions, their traditional function was to serve a pedagogical role within the discipline (e.g., Danziger, 1994). This function precludes historical studies from contributing to psychology as a disci- plinary project and constitutes a mobilization of the tradition for the purposes of celebrating the accomplishments of the past and justifying the present. Such repre- sentations of the past are premised on the continuity of the present. On an aesthetic reading such histories are the least interesting and most conventional. They reflect RECONSTRUCTING THE SUBJECT 29 the discipline as we have come to understand it, without in any way illuminating the subject matter of the discipline, namely the nature of human psychology itself. What Danziger has demonstrated with his histories of psychology is a way of proceeding that allows us to turn history on the subject matter of psychology itself. In this respect psychological studies are always historical; they reflect the formalization of language and the development of techniques that emerge out of our shared cultural goods. In that sense they do not entirely escape their origins in particular life-worlds. For even when we apply such routine tools as statistics to our psychological topics we do not escape a concern with number, efficiency, normativity and so on that are entailed in such devices . 5 CONCLUSIONS Disciplinary histories are specialized forms of history but history nonetheless. What Danziger’s work makes so clear with respect to Collingwood’s claim that it is the community of historians that ultimately regulates the work of the historian, is that likewise, it is the community of psychologists that regulates the work of the psychologist. What we do not know is, which discipline is to be regulative for the history of psychology. It is here that we can see the argument most clearly, for it is those who are wedded to a progressivist or positivist notion of history that see a limited role for that history and wish that history to be on bended knee before the scientific authority of psychology . 6 But the respect and authority of science can never be granted to a historical account of it, even if that history is merely ‘celebratory’ or presentist. For history cannot be science, in the same way that history is never just literature. It is here that psychology and history come together, for in order to know what the institution of psychology is we must have a history of it as it has been practiced. Yet the history of psychology already presupposes that we know what psychology in fact is. Hence the inseparability of the enterprise of determining the subject matter of psychology from its history. The story we tell about psychology is always both a historical and an implicitly teleological one. Critical historians of psychology have shifted their allegiance and they are no longer beholden to the scientific claims of the discipline. After all, these are exactly what need to be understood again from a historical perspective. Their regulative community exists elsewhere, in the history of science, within the community of critical psychologists, and so on. Hence their histories contribute theory to different communities with different sensibilities and criteria for knowledge. It is not that these communities necessarily speak incommensurate languages, but there are recognizable differences. It is Professor Danziger who is among the very best of those who have shown us that the picture of paradise created by traditional psychological histories was illusory and having tasted the forbidden fruit of critical 30 H. J. STAM historical knowledge there is no return from the exile in which we find ourselves. The vision in Danziger’s work then consists of a discipline that is no longer fettered to the chains of an epistemology that constricts our theoretical claims at every turn. In his own words, . . . changes in psychological categories will continue to be heavily dependent on changes in the societies within which these categories have a role. Their meaning will continue to be negotiated and contested among the groups to whom they matter. (Danziger, 1997a, p. 193) To end where I began, I would like to close this chapter with another anecdote: several years ago I attended a conference in Canada and was engaged in conver- sation by a retired colleague from a western Canadian university. He asked me to recommend some historical works on a particular topic and, as luck would have it, he just happened upon a topic that allowed me to rattle off a series of book titles. Impressed, he inquired, “Weren’t you a graduate student of Kurt Danziger’s?” I had to disappoint him and told him that no, I had studied with the late Nick Spanos, who although having had historical interests, was better known for his critical work on hypnosis and multiple personality. My colleague seemed disappointed but I took it as a compliment. I can only hope that Professor Danziger takes it the same way. NOTES 1 Department of Psychology, University of Calgary, Calgary, Alberta, Canada T2N 1N4. An earlier version of this paper was presented at a symposium in honor of Kurt Danziger at the European Society for the History of the Human Sciences meetings, Berlin, Germany, August 2000. I thank Adrian Brock and the organizers of that symposium for inviting me to participate and I am grateful to Kurt Danziger and the Editors for their generous comments on earlier drafts. 2 I should add here that I do not wish to denigrate Boring’s contributions to the institutional de- velopment of the history of psychology, especially with regard to the important role he played in legitimating historical studies as a pursuit within psychology. Boring could also be ambivalent in his presentism: “a psychological sophistication that contains no component of historical orientation seems to me to be no sophistication at all” (1929, p. vii). 3 Or even of criticizing “celebratory” accounts in favor of “condemnatory” accounts (Dehue, 1998). 4 Connelly and Costal (2000) have recently argued that Collingwood’s ideas on history also contained a version of a historical psychology that remains largely unelaborated. 5 One reviewer of this chapter noted that this and other descriptions makes it appear that Danziger’s work has something in common with the French Annales school which formed around Fernand Braudel in the 1950s and 60s. Known for its ‘total’ approach to history, there were no details of daily life too large or too small to contribute to historical accounts (often called ‘social history’). Braudel was famous for wishing to break down the boundaries of the social sciences in the name of an ‘interscience.’ Nonetheless, Danziger does not share the school’s penchant for economic explanations and the need for structural accounts, however sophisticated. Furthermore, intellectual work must always be more than the product of economic and social history since it is constituted in an international discourse that is continually contested across large geographical, social and economic domains. 6 Kendler’s (1987) textbook is perhaps one of the clearest examples of this. RECONSTRUCTING THE SUBJECT 31 REFERENCES Ankersmit, F. R. (1996). Aesthetic politics: Political philosophy beyond fact and value. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Ankersmit, F. R. (2002). Representational democracy: An aesthetic approach to conflict and compro- mise. Common Knowledge, 5(1), 24—46. Ash, M. G. (1993). Rhetoric, society, and the historiography of psychology. In H. V. Rappard, P. van Strien, L. P. Mos & W. J. Baker (Eds.), Annals of Theoretical Psychology, Vol. 8 (pp. 49-57). New York: Plenum. Bhaskar, R. (1978). A realist theory of science. Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press. Boring, E. G. (1929). A history of experimental psychology. New York: Century Co. Boring, E. G. (1961). Psychologist at large. New York: Basic Books. Collingwood, R. G. (1924). Speculum mentis. Oxford: Clarendon. Collingwood, R. G. (1946). The idea of history. Oxford: Clarendon. Collingwood, R. G. (1965). Essays in the philosophy of history , edited with an introduction by W. Debbins. Austin, Tex.: University of Texas Press. Connelly, J. & Costal, A. (2000). R. G. Collingwood and the idea of a historical psychology. Theory & Psychology, 10, 147-170. Danziger, K. (1990a). Constructing the subject: Historical origins of psychological research. Cam- bridge: Cambridge University Press. Danziger, K. (1990b). The social context of research practice and the history of psychology. In W. J. Baker, M. E. Hyland, R. van Hezewijk & S. Terwee (Eds.), Recent trends in theoretical psychology, Vol. II (pp. 297-303). New York: Springer- Verlag. Danziger, K. (1993a). Psychological objects, practice, and history. In H. V. Rappard, P. van Strien, L. P. Mos & W. J. Baker (Eds.), Annals of Theoretical Psychology, Vol. 8 (pp. 15 — 47). New York: Plenum. Danziger, K. (1993b). History, practice, and psychological objects: Reply to commentators. In H. V. Rappard, P. van Strien, L. P. Mos & W. J. Baker (Eds.), Annals of Theoretical Psychology, Vol. 8 (pp. 71-84). New York: Plenum. Danziger, K. (1994). Does the history of psychology have a future? Theory & Psychology, 4, 467-484. Danziger, K. (1997a). Naming the mind: How psychology found its language. London: Sage Publications. Danziger, K. (1997b). The future of psychology’s history is not its past: A reply to Rappard. Theory & Psychology, 7, 107-111. Danziger, K. (1998). On historical scholarship: A reply to Dehue. Theory & Psychology, 8, 669-671. Dehue, T. ( 1 998). Community historians and the dilemma of rigor vs relevance: A comment on Danziger and Van Rappard. Theory & Psychology, 8, 653-661. Fox-Genovese, E. & Lasch-Quinn, E. (Eds.) (1999). Reconstructing history. New York: Routledge. Goldstein, L. J. (1970). Collingwood’s theory of historical knowing. History and Theory, 9, 3-36. Hacking, I. (1994). The looping effects of human kinds. In D. Sperber, D. Premack & A. J. Premack (Eds.), Causal cognition: A multi-disciplinary approach (pp. 351-383). Oxford: Clarendon Press. Hanson, N. R. (1958). Patterns of discovery. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kendler, H. H. (1987). Historical foundations of modern psychology. Pacific Grove, CA: Brooks/Cole. Kuhn, T. S. (1970). The structure of scientific revolutions, 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Latour, B. (1993). We have never been modem. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. Losee, J. (1980). A historical introduction to the philosophy of science, 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Makkreel, R. A. (1992). Dilthey: Philosopher of the human studies. Princeton, N.J. Princeton University Press. 32 H. J. STAM Mills, J. (1993). Contextualizing Danziger within sociological theory. In H. V. Rappard, P. van Strien, L. R Mos & W. J. Baker (Eds.), Annals of Theoretical Psychology, Vol. 8 (pp. 65-70). New York: Plenum. Mos, L. P. (1996). Immanent critique of experience: Dilthey’s hermeneutics. In C. Tolman, F. Cherry, R. van Hezewijk, & I. Lubek (Eds.), Problems of theoretical psychology (pp. 368-377). Toronto: Captus. Rappard, J. F. H. van (1997). History of psychology turned inside(r) out: A comment on Danziger. Theory & Psychology, 7, 101-105. Ricoeur, P. (1984). Time and narrative, Vol. 1. (K. McLaughlin & D. Pellauer, trans.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Ricoeur, P. (1988). Time and narrative, Vol. 3. (K. Blarney & D. Pellauer, trans.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Stam, H. J. (1992). Deconstructing the subject: Banishing the Ghost of Boring. [Review of Construct- ing the subject: Historical origins of psychological research]. Contemporary Psychology, 37, 629-632. Stam, H. J. (1996). Theory & practice. In C. Tolman, F. Cherry, R. v. Hezewijk, & I. Lubek (Eds.), Problems of Theoretical Psychology (pp. 24-32). Toronto: Captus Press. Stam, H. J. (2000). Theoretical Psychology. In K. Pawlik & M. R. Rosenzweig (Eds.), International Handbook of Psychology (pp. 551-569). London: Sage. Stam, H. J. (2003). Retrieving the past for the future: Boundary maintenance in historical and theoretical psychology. In D. B. Hill and M. J. Krall (Eds.), About psychology: Essays at the crossroads of history, theory, and philosophy (pp. 147-163). New York: SUNY Press. Stam, H. J., Lubek, I. & Radtke, H. L. (2000). Strains in experimental social psychology: A textual analysis of the development of experimentation in social psychology. Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, 36, 365-382. Weimer, W. B. (1979). Notes on the methodology of scientific research. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum. White, H. (1973). Metahistory. Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press. White, H. (1978). Tropics of discourse. Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press. Chapter 2 IN SEARCH OF METHOD Johann Louw INTRODUCTION Since the early 1980s the historiography of psychology has undergone a significant transformation. The social contextualization of the history of psychology has been a defining component of this change, the acknowledgement of and search for the historical roots of psychological knowledge in specific social settings. One of the first publications to explore and plead for a recognition of the social origins of modern psychology was the edited book, Psychology in Social Context (Buss, 1979). The title of this volume, and the aims outlined in its opening chapter, signal its debt to the sociology of knowledge. Buss stated that Psychology as practiced by professional academicians occurs within a social context; psychological knowledge is tied to the infrastructure of a society of socially defined groups, (p. 2) As a social activity, the construction of knowledge also has a historical dimen- sion: To properly understand and evaluate the validity of ideas, theories, and concepts of psychology, one must adopt a sociohistoric interpretation, (p. ix) Thus psychology had to pay attention to its social basis, and had to acknowledge that external forces had an impact on internal developments in the discipline. In this essay I wish to return to the influence of the sociology of knowl- edge on these early developments. I will argue that this tradition can still be recognized in current debates, even if it is just in the recognition of overtones of constructivist epistemologies in them. Certainly, the “contextualist” analysis of psychological concepts and methods extends the tradition in some versions of 33 34 JOHANN LOUW social constructionism. The work of Kurt Danziger has played no small part in this process, and his chapter in Buss (1979) forms a pivotal transition point in his own work on the history of psychology. Indeed, his curriculum vitae shows a clear break around this time: he published this chapter (1979a), and “The pos- itivist repudiation of Wundt” (1979b), and since then has published only in the history of psychology. The chapter in Psychology in Social Context in particular forms a bridge between his interest prior to his first publications in the history of psychology and subsequent publications. The present chapter will address the work done prior to his switch to history and theory, mostly in South Africa before 1965. The key point here is that much of his South African work reflects a strong background in the sociology of knowledge, in which the figure of Karl Mannheim has loomed large. It will be argued that there are a number of continuities between these early publications and his historical/theoretical work. I will attempt to show that Danziger was steeped in this tradition long before he turned to history and the- ory of psychology. Indeed, one conclusion will be that his approach is consistently “sociological”, and that the early work on empirical aspects of the sociology of knowledge informed his later work on the history and theory of psychology. SOCIOLOGY OF KNOWLEDGE What is the nature of the link between the kinds of knowledge produced and the social conditions under which it is produced? How are such relationships in- vestigated? These are questions about the social roots of intellectual structures, which typically resort under the sociology of knowledge. Karl Mannheim has been a central figure in the study of the relationship between ideas and the struc- ture of society. He defined one of the foremost problems of the sociology of knowledge as how and in what form did all the ways of thinking, currents of thought, meanings of concepts, and categories of thought come about that constitute the present state of our knowledge and the totality of our world views? (1986, p. 48-9) In response to the epistemological question mentioned above, he arrived at the concept of “style” to group together ideas in terms of their form and content (Nelson, 1992). Ideational trends can be regarded as styles of thought, and he proposed that the analysis of styles of thought formed the basis of the sociology of knowledge. The empirical task for the sociology of knowledge was to reconstruct its historical and social roots; to explore the change of forms in this style of thought in relation to the social fates of the bearing groups. (Mannheim, 1986, p. 189, emphasis in original) IN SEARCH OF METHOD 35 These styles are borne by specific social groups in response to their experiential conditions, influenced by that group’s standing in wider society at a particular time in history. This is a formulation of social context as something socio-historical. Mannheim’s book on conservative thought was supposed to work out what an empirical sociology would look like. Nevertheless, his approach to the sociology of knowledge did not deliver fully on its empirical promise. After a reconstruction of Mannheim’s research program, Nelson (1992) concludes that such a program could be realized, and that Danziger’s work (1963b) in this tradition points to the way forward. DANZIGER’S EMPIRICAL INVESTIGATIONS OF STYLES OF THOUGHT How does one study long-term psychological changes that are important in a historical context? How does one investigate empirically how macro-social factors and the development of knowledge are related? These are the methodological questions Danziger posed in the 1950s and 1960s, when he turned to Mannheim’s sociology of knowledge (e.g. 1936) as a source of inspiration. In one sense, South Africa presented an ideal “context” to investigate such questions. Social relations in the country were troubled and insecure. In Ideology and Utopia Mannheim analyzed a not too dissimilar state of affairs in the Weimar Republic, about an intellectual crisis situation within the context of a social and political crisis in the latter stages of the Republic. According to Nelson, Mannheim argued that in situations of group conflict the underlying worldviews, or more exactly the funda- mental designs, of the groups involved will form the cognitive basis for the articulation of styles of thought that explicitly defend the reactive or proactive lifestyle ‘com- mitments’ of the groups. Large-scale economic changes which displace the mode of living of social groups stimulate the production of styles of thought as groups realize that their existing ways of life are threatened. (1992, p. 36) In all the studies discussed below, Danziger used existing socially-defined “race” groups in South Africa to produce the material for analysis. The reasons for this he gave himself (Danziger, 1963b). Firstly, there are historically specific factors that made race important in South Africa. Secondly, the social distribution of privileges occurs along racial lines, and is maintained by making race the principal administrative concept. Thirdly, race extends to all aspects of life; in fact, it is the foundation concept of the social and political order in South Africa. It was a society where no compromises were made about its racial structure, and where economic, political and social positions were rigidly defined. This made it relatively easy to detect and describe different styles of thought. Following Mannheim then, different 36 JOHANN LOUW groups in South Africa ought to hold different social theories, and the question becomes an empirical one: how to detect them in different groups. Three studies led up to Danziger’s “Ideology and Utopia” paper ( 1963a). In the first study (1958a), Danziger started to explore the association between the social position of a group and its view of social structure and social causation. He asked two groups of students, whites and blacks, to write an autobiographical essay, imagining themselves in 50 years time. Thus it was an autobiography projected into the future, to allow them greater opportunity to discuss their lives in a wider social setting, and to obtain information about their life goals and aspirations. By asking participants to focus on the future rather than the present or the past, the instructions managed to avoid any argument over which view was “objectively correct” — a problem for the sociology of knowledge throughout its history. Earlier Allport and Gillespie (1955) also asked students to write about their plans, hopes and aspirations for the future, and this work followed that practice. In a later paper (1963c) Danziger thanked Allport and Gillespie for making available their sample of South African autobiographies. Danziger however also was interested in individual processes, such as how manifestations of group differences entered into the personality of individuals. If they did, it ought to be possible to show empirically that individuals from different social groups differed in the values they held and the goals they set for themselves. To explore personal values, respondents were asked to respond to questions such as: “For what end would you be willing to make the greatest sacrifice of personal comfort, time, and money? (1958a, p. 318).” One of the consistent differences between the white and black (black African and Indian) students was that white students were concerned with private goals and aspirations, while black students mentioned benefits to their communities much more frequently, and had aspirations to serve that community. Allport and Gillespie (1955) similarly found a greater degree of what they called “privatism” among Americans, white South Africans, and New Zealanders, than among Egyptians, black South Africans, and Mexicans. In a follow-up part of the study, these main results were given to the students a few months later and they were asked to account for them. The groups also differed in terms of the explanations they gave for this finding. Whites tended to explain the differences that emerged in terms that downplayed the existence of conflict between groups: they ascribed the differences mainly to factors related to group inferiority, and group traditions. Blacks gave more conflict type explanations for these differences, such as political and economic discrimination, and barriers to individual achievement. Thus it seemed as if the groups adhered to two types of social causation, tied to their position in society. These findings provided support for some of the basic premises of the so- ciology of knowledge, Danziger argued. Whites, as beneficiaries of the social arrangement, were more conservative in their outlook, while blacks stressed the factor of social conflict, with the implication that things might change. Mannheim IN SEARCH OF METHOD 37 defined ideology as “those complexes of ideas which direct activity toward the maintenance of the prevailing order” and utopia as “those complexes of ideas which tend to generate activities toward changes of the prevailing order (Wirth, 1936, p. xxiii). The white group’s dislike of social change led them to deny the element of social conflict with its possibilities of social change (ideology), and the black group stressed conflict, with the resulting possibilities of change (utopia). Indeed, one might say that a difference of implicit social theory has been detected, in terms of how people conceive the structure of society and the relationships between groups. In the second paper (1958b), group differences in the definition of the social situation were examined. In South Africa, this meant examining the evaluation by whites and blacks of the dominant pattern of their society, captured by the term “white civilization”. White and black students were presented with a list of 14 features which “different people have claimed to be highly characteristic of white civilization in South Africa” (Danziger, 1958b, p. 340). They were asked to indicate which of these features they considered to be really characteristic of white civilization and which not. In addition, they were asked to respond to the same questions identified in the previous paper, and to complete an abbreviated version of Adorno’s F scale. Once again, differences in “styles of thought” could indeed be demonstrated between privileged and non-privileged groups in South Africa. Whites, as the beneficiaries of the social order (i.e. “white civilization”), overall tended to evaluate it more favorably than blacks, whom the system reduced to second class citizens. It showed also why South Africa was such a good example to study, because of the domination of a white minority over power. In a homogeneous society members shared a much more common definition of their social situation: “their position in the world, their goals and how to achieve them; they have a similar evaluation of their society as a whole and of their position in it” (Danziger, 1958b, p. 339). In a society split by conflict, opposing groups could be expected to define the social situation very differently. The existence of styles of thought did not rule out the possibility that sub- systems existed within groups as well. Danziger examined differences within the white group, and found that the proportion of favorable valuations was much less among university students than among technical college students. The technical college students, Danziger speculated, might be more representative of the popu- lation as a whole, while the university students came under the influence of a more critical attitude at university. Differences also occurred within the black group: the proportion of unfavorable evaluations was slightly greater among African than Indian respondents. Africans had even fewer civil rights in South Africa than Indian respondents, and this difference in social position could explain this result. Furthermore, the groups differed in the nature of the favorable items they chose to characterize “white civilization”. Whites chose items such as “high 38 JOHANN LOUW standards of morality in the sphere of family life”, and “respect for law and order”. This indicates that they perceived the social order as moral and just, as “white civilization” could claim some moral advantage. Blacks were only prepared to concede that it delivered material advantages to whites, by choosing items like “a superior system for the production of material goods”. They rejected its claims to moral excellence; in fact, they rated it as immoral and unjust, by choosing items like “unjust oppression of nonwhite people”. Phrased in more psychological terms, one could say that this is a difference in attitude, but “attitude” is conceived in a much more holistic and social fashion in this study than was the case in the more typical attitude surveys of the time. Answers to the questions about personal values confirmed the previous finding that whites are more “privatistic” and blacks more “communal”. How to understand this link? Danziger suggested that a group’s orientation was determined by “certain positive pressures towards redressing real and perceived limitations on the group by means of group action.” In less privileged groups, who were discriminated against, members “tend to internalize the social aspirations of the group so as to turn them into individual aspirations for each member” (Danziger, 1958b, p. 343). This convergence of social and individual goals occurred when the social system limited or blocked individual aspirations, simply because of the group they belonged to. For dominant groups, on the other hand, a conflict between public duty and individual interests emerged. For example, none of the white respondents mentioned a change in the social order as one of their personal desires. Some of them recognized the injustice of this order, so for these respondents there was a discrepancy between the definition of the social order and their personal aspirations. Whites resolved this by agreeing with statements about “abstract helpfulness”, such as “reducing human unhappiness”. The commitment therefore remained abstract and imprecise, which was quite convenient, because it was unlikely to lead to action. The more specific the social aim, the more likely it would lead to social action. In line with this, the black respondents mentioned aspects of specific helpfulness much more frequently, e.g. “establish a clinic in an African area”. As long as the aim remains abstract and formal, its function may not really be that of re-orientating the individual towards social action, but rather that of assuaging the guilt that arises from the conflict between social ideals and private interest. For the socially oriented person, on the other hand, social aims naturally assume a concrete content, as they arise directly out of the demands of a specific external situation that have become identified with his individual interest, (ibid.) Those white participants who gave the most favorable responses to “white civilization” tended to get higher scores on the F scale, as one could predict. Their acceptance of social discrimination and approval of the existing social situation were linked with authoritarian values and fascism as estimated by the F-scale. In the black group, authoritarian values were frequently associated with a critical IN SEARCH OF METHOD 39 attitude to the existing social order, which Danziger argued had to do with the need for group solidarity. Thus one had authoritarian values espoused by both white and black groups, but for totally different reasons. To explain this, one had to go beyond the narrow confines of psychology again: “The interpretation of the pattern of ‘authoritarianism’ must always take into account the wider social context” (Danziger, 1958b, p. 345). In the third paper, Danziger (1963a) used the future autobiographies as a method of assessing another aspect of the inter-relationship between macro-social factors and ideas. “Economic growth”, and the differences in growth patterns be- tween countries, were not areas in which social psychologists showed much of an interest. Apart from McClelland’s work on achievement motivation, psycholo- gists had little to say about the requirements of economic growth, particularly in “under-developed” countries. The question then becomes how to investigate psychological factors that are associated with sociological factors involved in economic growth. The future auto- biographies were seen as a promising technique to measure the presence of “action tendencies” (Danziger, 1963a, p. 17) in individuals, which could be linked to certain sociological factors, such as participation in modern economic and administrative processes. The action tendency in this study turned out to be the tendency toward self-rationalization. Max Weber (1947) identified one of the core components of modernization in terms of a growing process of rationalization of various spheres of society. It is characterized by elements such as specialized institutions, the adoption of bureau- cratic standards, the separation of private and public, and secularization. Danziger used the term rationalization to indicate the organization of “actions into a system which constitutes the optimum arrangement of means for bringing about a certain end” (Danziger, 1963a, p. 17). In such a system custom was no longer blindly accepted as a justification for organizing society, and was gradually extended, as the economy in these countries became more industrialized and administration more bureaucratized. As larger areas of social life are rationalized, individuals become “rational- ized” as well. Mannheim (1940) recognized this, and called the change in the individual’s own attitude to his/her life “self-rationalization”. Life has to be seen as a long-term enterprise, in which each step has to be planned and calculated in terms of how it will contribute to achieving ultimate goals. The criterion for the rationality of the actions of individuals in this context was how it contributed to career success. It involved the “calculating control of impulse in the interests of a deliberately formulated life-plan” (Danziger, 1971, p. 292). For Danziger, this implied a rigorous control of impulse, and the application of a strict, objective time scheme to one’s life. It stands to reason that individuals would differ in the degree to which they manifested these tendencies, and it should therefore be possible to measure these individual differences. Self-rationalization is associated with larger 40 JOHANN LOUW social processes through a group’s involvement in rationalized economic and ad- ministrative processes. Where members of a group have been exposed to such processes over a long period of time, higher levels of self-rationalization should be present when compared to groups where this exposure has been recent and incomplete, argued Danziger. The instructions for the autobiographies were slightly different from before. Students were asked to begin at the present, and to write a few paragraphs concern- ing their expectations, plans and aspirations for the future. From these essays, an index of self-rationalization was calculated from 7 variables, such as: ego-reality statements (realistic statements about the writer’s personal future); non-career values (the writer’s commitment to values that conflict with the pursuit of pure self-interest); objective time reference (rationing of time for its most efficient use); and time structure (the number of distinct stages on the life path). The presence of these seven variables in the biographies was scored and weighted, resulting in a scale on which 25 was the highest possible score and 0 the lowest. Individuals who were high in self-rationalization would exhibit a very realistic level of planning, a relative absence of unrealistic fantasy and of non-career goals, a concentration on personal rather than community goals, a pre- occupation with economic incentives, and the use of a well-articulated temporal structure shown by precise time references and orderly succession of life stages. (Danziger, 1971, p. 292) The hypothesis that participation in rationalized economic and administrative processes will be substantially related to self-rationalization was supported. First, African males manifested a far lower level of self-rationalization than English- speaking white males because, Danziger argued, of their incomplete involvement in rationalized social institutions and the special limitations imposed upon them by an irrational system of social domination. When compared to Allport and Gillespie’s (1955) data, these differences between black and white South Africans ran parallel to the differences between respondents from highly developed and the “underde- veloped” countries these authors used. Furthermore, Allport and Gillespie showed Afrikaans-speaking students to be significantly below English-speaking students on the mean index of self-rationalization, reflecting their differences in degree of involvement in the modernizing sectors of the economy. By the time of Danziger’s study, however, this difference was no longer significant, in line with Afrikaans speakers’ increasing participation in the modernizing economy. Thus the future autobiography seemed to provide a technique for objectively assessing a pattern of rationalization in large groups of respondents. Once such a technique was available, it became possible to investigate the psychological aspects of the pattern of self-rationalization. In this paper the economy was brought into reciprocal influence relation with the psychology of the individual. IN SEARCH OF METHOD 41 The key paper in this series was published in 1963(b). The title, “Ideology and Utopia in South Africa” was a deliberate reference to Mannheim: “I called the paper in the British journal ‘Ideology and Utopia in South Africa’ which is a direct take on Mannheim’s book” (Danziger, in Brock, 1995, p. 13). He asked (mostly) university students (84 African, 51 Indian, 53 Afrikaans-speaking white, and 251 English-speaking white) to write essays projecting future social changes in South Africa (Danziger, 1963b, pp. 65-66). From these “future histories” he analyzed the styles of thought of the different social groups. For the analysis of the future autobiographies collected in this study, he devised a five-fold typology of styles of thought, or dominant type of historical orientation: Conservative; Technicist; Catastrophic; Liberal; and Revolutionary. The assignment of student writing content to one of these styles was determined by the presence of four characteristics in their essays: (a) the attitude to and inter- relationship of the present and the future; (b) interrelationship of historical means and ends; (c) the conception of social change; and (d) the conception of social causality. The essay was assigned to one of the five types in terms of which one occurred most frequently in terms of the four criteria. The Afrikaans-speaking white students mostly exhibited Conservative and Technicist orientations to the future, while English-speaking whites were mostly Catastrophic and Conservative in their orientation. Indian students were Liberal and Revolutionary, while African students were Revolutionary and Liberal. Thus “the frequency of the various types of historical orientation conforms broadly to the position of the different groups in the social structure” (1963b, p. 70). The Afrikaans- speaking group was at the head of the power hierarchy and had the highest frequency of conservative types, while the African group, which was lowest in the hierarchy, produced the highest frequency of revolutionary types. As in the 1958(b) paper, findings clearly showed that differences existed within groups as well. Afrikaans-speaking white students, for example, who tended to adopt either conservative or technicist historical orientations, included some catastrophic or liberal orientations. In addition, the extent of this range varies for different groups at different times. In societies that were undergoing rapid social change, Danziger believed future autobiographies provided a valuable technique for establishing “the crucial links between changes in social structure and changes in personality structure” (p. 27). These studies showed clearly that it was possible to detect differences in con- temporary thought styles, especially in highly stratified, unstable societies, using empirical methods as described. Danziger came to the conclusion that the range of available thought was socially determined, and that social position determined the range of available historical orientations for the members of each group. Further- more, the situationally transcendent ideas that were identified could be regarded as attempts at subjectively mastering the basic tensions in society. 42 JOHANN LOUW In 1963 samples from future biographies collected in 1952, 1956 and 1962 from a total of 162 African high school students were analyzed. Danziger (1963c) had no less a target than a “historical psychology” in his sights; a psychology concerned with “that deeper surge of change represented by the reconstruction of values and perspectives in the context of complex historical developments” (p. 31). The application of quantitative methods of content analysis in this regard was very different from the conventional employment of these methods. At the time that the first autobiographies were collected, apartheid still had some degree of flexibility, though it became more and more coercive and uncom- promising as the years progressed. By 1962, the last time that the autobiographies were collected, the lives of black Africans were under the complete control of the apartheid system. In 1961 political activity in the black community went un- derground, and acts of sabotage began toward the end of 1961. This led to more repressive measures from the apartheid state. The empirical question in this pub- lication was: How would these changes in imposed social control and repression affect the psychological future of African high schoolers? The results again provided support for an interpretation sympathetic to the so- ciology of knowledge. For a start, a massive majority of essays expressed complete opposition to government policies, with not a single statement of identification with the system. Forty-six percent predicted a violent overthrow of the regime. These percentages did not change from 1950 to 1962. There was also a consistent in- crease in a preoccupation with socio-political problems, and a tendency to see the future in social rather than individual terms. It is not too difficult to see these devel- opments as reactions to changing conditions of political repression. The content of the psychological future as reflected in the future autobiographies also changed as a result of these structural changes. Both the goals of economic success and community service declined over time, to be replaced by political activity goals, expressed in the cause of African nationalism. “The intensification of authoritarian political control is having the effect on the individual educated African of defining his future in political terms” (Danziger, 1963c, p. 39). These empirical studies were conducted during one of South Africa’s most politically repressive periods. The National Party had started to implement its apartheid policies vigorously and systematically since its election into power in 1948, which led to large-scale confrontations with black resistance organi- zations in the 1950s and 1960s. Thus this period of extreme social instability in the country was an almost ideal-typical setting to examine Mannheim’s theories regarding the role of situationally transcendent ideas about the future of society. Apartheid ideology and practice structured racial and political consciousness of different groups to such an extent that they failed to develop a shared style of thought. For the most part whites saw the situation as “normal” and generally acceptable, while blacks saw it as ripe for radical change. Danziger’s empiri- cally based historical psychology reconstructed the social and historical roots IN SEARCH OF METHOD 43 of these ideologies and utopias in terms of the positions of the groups holding them. The discussion of these studies identified and emphasized the sociological in- fluences in Danziger’s work. But what about psychological influences? The social psychology of Kurt Lewin certainly deserves some mention in this regard. One clue to its influence on the early work of Danziger is provided by the prominence given in his empirical papers to “the psychological future” as experienced by re- spondents. Danziger hypothesized that one of his findings, the decline of the use of a temporal framework by his black respondents, could be explained in terms of special limitations placed on them from 1950 to 1962. He ascribed to Lewin (1954) the hypothesis that a decline in the “differentiation of the psychological future may well be the result of externally imposed frustration” (Danziger, 1963c, p. 37). In Lewin’s work, the psychological meaning of actions was emphasized, which was derived from the larger structure within which such actions were em- bedded. For example, the state of the person and that of his/her environment were not independent of each other — the person lived in a psychological environment (Lewin, 1954, p. 918). For Lewin the behavior of a person always was part of the larger situation, and thus the object of investigation in psychology had to be the “person-in-a-situation”. The psychological meaning of an action therefore was not fixed, but depended on the context within which it occurred. For example, in Lewin’s studies in the 1930s at Iowa on “group climates” (Lewin, Lippitt & White, 1939), major differences emerged between the boys in the “authoritarian”, “demo- cratic”, and “laissez-faire” conditions. In other words, differences in their behavior depended on differences in the social conditions in which they found themselves. Additional resemblances between Lewin’s and Danziger’s work are the ten- dency to confront significant social issues in their research, and the acknowledge- ment that human actions take place in a temporal domain as well, rather than being a characteristic of a static “personality”. Lewin’s work formed a bridge to Gestalt psychology for Danziger. His work on group climates point to Lewin’s preference to work with holistic units in a non- elementaristic fashion. Individuals were not studied in isolation, but as participants in whole situations. As Danziger wrote in Constructing the Subject about Lewin, “types of psychological context” (p. 177) rather than individuals become the real objects of psychological investigation. Another linkage to Gestalt theory is through Solomon Asch’s attempt to develop a psychology of social life through using Gestalt theory. For Asch, one level of human motivation was that human beings “crave society” (1952, p. 324) — they have a “social interest”. Behaviorist and psychoanalytic theories of social interest firstly find no place for precisely the phenomenon with which enquiry should begin — the presence of a direct overflowing interest in other human beings, in the life of groups, and in the need to participate actively in them. (p. 332) 44 JOHANN LOUW From this brief discussion of psychological influences in the early empirical work in the sociology of knowledge tradition, one can say that they were European rather than Anglo-American in origin, despite the fact that Danziger received his formal training in the latter. FURTHER EMPIRICAL STUDIES In the 1980s and ‘90s a number of studies revisited Danziger’s empirical so- ciology of knowledge approach, to study psychological concomitants of political change in South Africa. Du Preez, Bhana, Broekmann, Louw and Nel (1981), Louw (1983) and Du Preez and Collins (1985) provided time series data on so- cial orientation. They established that Afrikaans-speaking whites had changed most over time, from a conservative position (nothing will change politically) to a liberal position (gradual, controlled change will take place). African and Indian groups changed the least in future orientation. In addition, there was no dom- inant or transcendent historical perspective that could unite all groups. Whites predominantly saw the future as catastrophic, while black groups were more op- timistic. These studies were conducted at a time when the country again was in turmoil, as a result of the apartheid state’s military response to black resistance, and in the mid-1980s several states of emergency were declared to quell popular uprisings. In February 1990 Nelson Mandela was released from prison into a very po- larized society. As the negotiations for a new political dispensation started, levels of violence actually increased, and were particularly high between 1992 and 1994. The political solution reached at these negotiations during the first part of the 1990s culminated in 1994 in the first democratic elections in South Africa. During this time, Finchilescu and Dawes (1999) asked adolescents, both prior to and after the foundation of democracy in South Africa, to write an essay in which they pre- dicted the future of South Africa in the next decade. Only two future scenarios appeared in the essays: Catastrophic and Liberal. The Revolutionary outcome vir- tually disappeared from the essays written by black African youth, and they now expected Liberal futures — society would be peacefully transformed under gov- ernment guidance. The orientations produced by coloured and Indian adolescents shifted from 1980 to 1996 to be more similar to whites than they were to Black Africans. These groups produced high percentages of essays with a Catastrophic orientation to the future: the future held chaos, violence, and social upheaval. Thus the authors established again that wide differences in the perceptions of the youths from the various population groups existed. Finally, there also were a large number of essays without clear future themes, many more than in previous studies. They ascribed the latter finding to the lack of a clearly defined structural conflict, and a state of confusion about the future. IN SEARCH OF METHOD 45 In these studies we again recognize the important elements of the historical- psychological approach Danziger had in mind earlier. The differences in the per- spectives between social groups, and the changes they represented, must be studied and understood “in the context of complex historical developments” (Danziger, 1963c, p. 31). IMPLICATIONS Danziger’s early empirical studies in the sociology of knowledge contain at least three continuities with his later work in the history and theory of psychology. These are concerns with history, context, and method. The first continuity refers to the recognition of history. Indeed, the strength of the sociology of knowledge, in Mannheim’s tradition, is its recognition of the im- portance of socially transcendent ideas — ideas that point to the past or the future. Danziger similarly concerned himself with the subjects’ temporal orientation — past, present, and future. He argued that the temporal dimension was in fact the dominant stylistic dimension, as events are ordered on a time scale (Danziger, 1963b). For example, a revolutionary style of thought emphasizes present ten- sions, which will be removed in future by social disruptions at one or more strate- gic moments. Thus a concern about the future of society, as indicated by future biographies or future histories, introduces temporal orientation as a dimension into empirical research. Context assumed two meanings in these publications. In one sense, Danziger worked in a specific political context himself, which allowed him research pos- sibilities not so available elsewhere. Two prominent aspects relating to the South African setting of this work can be identified. First, disciplinary boundaries were much less rigid than they were in American social science at the time. In an inter- view (Brock, 1995, p. 1 1) he said, referring to South Africa, That was the other thing that began to strike me at that time: the tremendous hold that disciplinary loyalties had on social psychologists in North America when compared to their counterparts in some other parts of the world. For us it really wasn't that important whether a person was a psychologist or a sociologist or an anthropologist. This made it easier to follow research avenues suggested by the sociology of knowledge when one looked for explanations of human actions. A second contextual factor linked South Africa to the recognition of history in this work. In the “underdeveloped” (as they were still called) countries of the world social relations often were unstable enough to cast doubt on how they could be maintained in future. Where the future of society was in doubt, situationally transcendent ideas flourished like in the Europe of old, Danziger argued. South Africa of the 1950s and 1 960s was a country where doubt about the future of society 46 JOHANN LOUW was intense, because few could see a way out of the conflicts created by the race- based policies of the government at the time. Rigid social distinctions based on race dominated all aspects of life, so much so that situationally transcendent ideas developed in the society could be expected to be virtually mutually exclusive, depending on the positions of the contending groups. This is a classic situation for the sociology of knowledge. Context also was used in a sense much closer to how it would be used later in historical-theoretical work. The 1958(a) paper recognized explicitly the possibility that social context may play a more important role in psychology than generally accepted. Black South Africans expressed a stronger desire for social equality and social freedom than for the satisfaction of immediate private needs, and this re- flects on psychological theories of human motivation. This is more in agreement with Asch, says Danziger, and less in agreement with some of the traditional biol- ogistic theories of motivation. In his Social Psychology , Asch (1952) identified the “biological doctrine” as one of the explanations of the social nature of human be- ings. This explanation entered psychology under the aegis of behaviorism, argued Asch, and as a result, human social actions were learned because “they bring the individual directly or indirectly the gratification of primary needs” (p. 13). For Danziger, however, there is another implication here: “one can only raise the ques- tion of the extent to which even supposedly scientific theories in psychology are affected by the social context in which they arise and flourish” (1958a, p. 323). Also, in explaining the pattern of authoritarianism exhibited by his respondents, the wider social context had to be taken into account (Danziger, 1958b, p. 345). Such a contextualist position is of course part and parcel of the sociology of knowledge, in which concepts have a basis in specifiable contexts. Methodologically, two aspects of these studies deserve mention. Danziger was searching for empirical methods in social psychology that were responsive to the factors of history and context. A major concern was that the methods used by social psychologists, in attitude surveys for example were too reductionistic. Attitude surveys normally start off with a collection of separate elements in order to arrive at a measure of the whole. In addition, they place respondents in the role of passive selectors of pre-structured categories. In Constructing the Subject, he pointed out that the standard laboratory experiment, with its emphasis on isolating individual “stimuli”, also was reductionistic in its approach. The value and attractiveness of Mannheim’s approach lay in its reversal of this practice: it was concerned with social totality, and with its active construction by social agents. Ideological or utopian attitudes were treated as wholes, since they arose when the future of society as a whole was in doubt. The meaning that social events had for the individual was determined partly by the kind of ordering used by the social groups s/he belonged to. South Africa again provided fertile ground to show that a tendency toward an individualist orientation and away from a socially oriented interpretation will lead IN SEARCH OF METHOD 47 to meager insights. The psychological aspects of personal lives in countries like South Africa often were of a secondary nature. There were larger scale, macro- sociological factors that had to be considered first. Also, to look for the starting point of social change at the level of individual motivation was simply a mistake. For example, in terms of factors retarding economic growth, he argued that As far as South Africa is concerned, one cannot dismiss the possibility that the forcible stifling of political aspirations is indirectly responsible for the low level of discipline, morale and enthusiasm of many African workers. (Danziger, 1963d, p. 397) Thus an understanding of “the problem of African workers’ productivity” cannot first be sought at an individual level. By the same token, however, sociological factors were not the only ones operating here. They interfaced in a complex pattern with individual characteristics of persons. Take for example the operation of laws that barred black people from advancing beyond the lowest level jobs: ... if no amount of personal achievement will lift the individual beyond the social status of a second-rate creature who is not capable of determining his own future, then we should not be surprised if interest in achievement remains at a low level. Large- scale individual efficiency and the maintenance of a system of social stratification based on inborn characteristics like skin color would seem to be largely incompatible. (p. 398) The challenge of conceptualizing the relationship between the individual and social interpretations of course remained with social psychology up to the present (see the discussion on levels of explanation below). In the chapter in Buss (1979), Danziger merges the three elements of history, context and method. History now takes central stage, for the first time in his pub- lication record. The methodological focal point now shifts away from empirical methods in social psychology to historiography: how to practice the history of psy- chology. In this practice, the influence of the sociology of knowledge is still clearly discernable. I have already indicated that Buss placed the text squarely within the sociology of psychological knowledge, in particular in the debate between “inter- nal” and “external” historians of psychology. Danziger approaches this debate by analyzing the institutionalization of American and German psychology. The rise of the discipline of psychology, Danziger argued, depended on the invention of a role that did not exist before, that of the professional practitioner of the new sci- ence. This new role depended on the society in which such roles were established, with the result that what was defined as “psychology” differed quite substantially between the USA and Germany. The reasons for this were clearly not just internal to the discipline. German and American psychologists had to take into account the norms and interests of existing power groups in their quest to institutionalize psy- chology, but the power groups psychologists had to address were very different in the two countries. In Germany, it was an academic and professional establishment 48 JOHANN LOUW dominated by philosophy. In the USA, however, universities and the resources they controlled were much more allied to the business sector, or to politics. The difference in social context determined the different forms that psychology took in quite fundamental ways in the USA and in Germany. In this connection Danziger evoked the concept of legitimation. This terminol- ogy too has its background in a publication on South Africa, when he published a paper (Danziger, 1971) in which analyzed strategies of legitimation of social power, using the successive legitimations of apartheid as a case in point. He now draws from a slightly different tradition in the sociology of knowledge, that estab- lished by Max Weber. INTELLECTUAL INTEREST In the examination of legitimation strategies that led to differences in the insti- tutionalization of psychology in Germany and the USA, Danziger tried to overcome the dualism created between internal and external factors in the development of the discipline. To accomplish this, he introduced an important historiographical device that would link these two opposing poles, in the concept of intellectual interest. Intellectual interest mediates between external and internal forces operating on the development of a discipline, he argued. It faces both inward and outward: outward, in that it serves to legitimate the activities of its practitioners vis-a-vis significant target groups; inward, in that it establishes the norms by which the work of practitioners is judged. (Danziger, 1979a, p. 38) In Germany, psychologists had to convince an academic and professional estab- lishment dominated by philosophy of the acceptability of the knowledge claims of the new discipline. In the USA, however, if psychology was to emerge as a recognized, independent discipline, it had to present itself as acceptable to busi- ness or political power groups. Thus psychologists presented themselves as the scientists of behavior, and ultimately had as their goal the “prediction and control of behavior”. Intellectual interest therefore is the instrument of legitimation, both “inter- nally” and “externally”. Internally, it holds together the practitioners of a field around the subject matter, goals and methods of the discipline. Outside the dis- cipline, it represents an attempt to convince powerful groups of the acceptability of the discipline’s work, because there is a compatibility of intellectual interests between the new discipline and these powerful groups. The concept of intellectual interest thus makes it possible to overcome the absolute separation of “social fac- tors” and “intellectual content”, that was so troublesome in a positivist sociology of science (e.g. Ben-David & Collins, 1966). Indeed, Danziger (1979a) turns to IN SEARCH OF METHOD 49 “intellectual interest” as a device to understand “context” after strongly criticizing the positivist approach of these two authors. In the 1980s Doise (1986) called this a problem of levels of explanation or analysis. Doise argued that by framing the relationship between the individual and the social in terms of a dualism, one faces the charge of reductionism at either extreme. He argued for four levels: • Intra-individual levels of analysis are normally characterized as “psycho- logical” explanations, such as the authoritarian personality. • Inter-individual or situational levels of analysis involve processes between individuals, such as social comparison theory. • Positional levels of analysis regard differences in position or social status, normally based on factors such as gender, race or class, to account for findings of a study • Ideological levels of analysis emphasize the general conceptions of social relations that serve to legitimize the existing social order. Those who criticized mainstream social psychology in the 1980s, at least as it was practiced in the USA, stated that it typically focused on the first two levels of analysis. The sociology of knowledge approach chosen by Danziger for the empirical studies in social psychology made it possible to include all four levels of analysis in the explanation of his findings. But the dualistic framing of a choice between inter- nal and external developments in psychology in the historiography of psychology also implied a level of analysis problem. What Danziger did by introducing the notion of intellectual interest was to reunite the internal and the external; to show that the problem arises when it is formulated in terms of a choice to be made. The tendency for psychology to give preference to individualistic levels of analysis has been discussed earlier. The sociology of knowledge, on the other hand, privileges macro-social structures, and social relationships within those structures. Sociol- ogists of knowledge generally imply that in the relationship between knowledge and society, “the social” has primacy. In his chapter in Buss (1979), Danziger tried for the first time to overcome this dualism in regard to the history of psychology by showing how the intellectual interests of the community of specialist psychologists will mediate the relationship between psychological knowledge and interests and structures in the wider society. CONCLUSION In later years, this way of surmounting implied dualisms via mediating de- vices, became quite a familiar way of working for Danziger. In Constructing the 50 JOHANN LOUW Subject (1990), and other publications (e.g. Danziger, 1993), he used the notion of investigative practices to perform a similar historiographical function to that of intellectual interest. Earlier he spoke of different patterns of investigative prac- tice, such as the Leipzig and Paris models, and “American innovations’’ (Danziger, 1985). Investigative practice has a logical dimension in guiding the research work of psychologists, but it also has a social dimension. For example: the individual investigator acts within a framework determined by the potential con- sumers of the products of his or her research and by the traditions of acceptable practice prevailing in the field. Moreover, the goals and knowledge interests that guide this practice depend on the social context within which investigators work. (1990, p. 4) The social context includes the pattern of social relations among investigators and their subjects, the norms of appropriate practice in the relevant research community, the kinds of knowledge interests that prevail at different times and places, and the relations of the research community with the broader social context that sustains it. (p. 5) This typical way of working can be discerned in Naming the Mind (Danziger, 1997) as well, where the growth of attitude research is ascribed to two main factors. The first of these came from outside the discipline in the form of public interest, while the second factor was internal to the discipline and involved finding a way to measure attitudes. Thus investigative practice becomes the primary medium through which social forces have shaped the discipline. Although investigative practices are claimed as the media through which so- cial interests have been reflected, the analysis in later years went a little further, to include the construction of psychological objects themselves, and how inves- tigative practices constituted such objects (Danziger, 1993). The embeddedness of psychology in extra-disciplinary contexts has implications for the very objects of psychological study. For example, with regard to personality and its assess- ment, Their construction of ‘personality ’ or ‘character" as an object of knowledge was strictly confined by the rather severe limitations of the social context in which their investigations originated. (Danziger, 1990, p. 171) To be perceived as legitimate, psychology and the objects of its study could not stray too far from the local cultural definitions of their task. And here we are back to the ideological component of psychological knowledge, that different aspects of psychology will be sanctioned by different societies, and that psychology will build its cultural values into its procedures. For Danziger, the world of psychology IN SEARCH OF METHOD 51 is a constructed world, and historians of psychology must study the constructive activities that produced it. REFERENCES Allport, G.W. & Gillespie, J.M. (1955). Youth’s outlook on the future. New York: Doubleday. Asch, S.E. (1952). Social psychology. Englewood-Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Ben-David, J. & Collins, R. (1966). Social factors in the origin of a new science: The case of psychology. American Sociological Review, 31, 45 1-465. Brock, A. (1995). An interview with Kurt Danziger. History and Philosophy of Psychology Bulletin, 7(2), 10-22. Buss, A.R. (Ed.) (1979). Psychology in social context. New York: Irvington. Danziger, K. (1958a). Self-interpretations of group differences in values. Journal of Social Psychology, 47, 317-325. Danziger, K. (1958b). Value differences among South African students. Journal of Abnormal & Social Psychology, 57, 339-346. Danziger, K. (1963a). Validation of a measure of self-rationalization. Journal of Social Psychology, 59, 17-28. Danziger, K. (1963b). Ideology and utopia in South Africa: A methodological contribution to the sociology of knowledge. British Journal of Sociology, 14, 59-76. Danziger, K. (1963c). The psychological future of an oppressed group. Social Forces, 42, 3 1 — 40. Danziger, K. (1963d). Some social psychological aspects of economic growth. South African Journal of Science, 59, 394-398. Danziger, K. (1971). Modernization and the legitimation of social power. In H. Adam (Ed.), South Africa. Sociological perspectives (pp. 283-300). London: Oxford University Press. Danziger, K. (1979a). The social origins of modem psychology. In A.R. Buss (Ed.), Psychology in social context (pp. 27-45). New York: Irvington. Danziger, K. (1979b). The positivist repudiation of Wundt. Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, 102, 143-148. Danziger, K. (1985). The origins of the psychological experiment. American Psychologist, 40, 133-140. Danziger, K. (1990). Constructing the subject. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Danziger, K. (1993). Psychological objects, practice, and history. Annals of Theoretical Psychology, 8, 15—47. Danziger, K. (1997). Naming the mind: How psychology found its language. London: Sage Publications. Doise, W. (1986). Levels of explanation in social psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Du Preez, P., Bhana, K., Broekmann, N., Louw, J. & Nel, E.M. (1981). Ideology and utopia revisited. Social Dynamics, 7, 52-55. Du Preez, P. & Collins, P. (1985). Ideology and utopia in South Africa: Twenty years after. South African Journal of Political Science, 12, 66-78. Finchilescu, G. & Dawes, A. (1999). Adolescents’ future ideologies through four decades of South African history. Social Dynamics, 25(2), 98-118. Lewin, K. (1954). Behavior and development as a function of the total situation. In L. Carmichael (Ed.), Manual of child psychology (pp. 919-970). New York: John Wiley. Lewin, K., Lippitt, R., & White, R. (1939). Patterns of aggressive behavior in experimentally created “social climates”. Journal of Social Psychology, 10, 271-299. Louw, J. (1983). Changing expectations of the future. In J.B. Deregowski, S. Dziurawiec & R.C. Annis (Eds.), Expiscations in cross-cultural psychology (pp. 403 — 413). Lisse: Swets and Zeitlinger. 52 JOHANN LOUW Mannheim, K. (1936). Ideology and utopia. London: Percy, Lund, Humphries & Company. Mannheim, K. (1940). Man and society. London: Kegan Paul. Mannheim, K. (1986). Conservatism. A contribution to the sociology of knowledge. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Nelson, R.D. (1992). The analysis of styles of thought. British Journal of Sociology, 43, 25-54. Weber, M. (1947). The theory of social and economic organization. London: Hodge. Wirth, L. (1936). Preface. In K. Mannheim, Ideology and utopia (pp. xiii-xxxi). London: Percy, Lund, Humphries & Company. Chapter 3 CONTROLLING THE METALANGUAGE AUTHORITY AND ACQUIESCENCE IN THE HISTORY OF METHOD Andrew S. Winston In Naming the Mind, Danziger (1997) analyzed the emergence of the fundamen- tal categories of psychological inquiry. Challenging the implicit assumption that behavior, personality, intelligence, learning, and motivation can be understood as natural kinds, he carefully explicated their origins and dynamics as negotiated products of scientific communities. In Chapter 9, he focused on the introduc- tion of the concept of variables in psychological discourse and how this change profoundly altered the shape of psychological inquiry during the 20th century. Danziger employed the term “metalanguage” to describe the shared discursive practices regarding method that came to be nearly universal in mainstream psy- chology, and indeed helped to define the mainstream. This aspect of Danziger’s work has overlapped with my own. Starting in 1988, I began to ask how the terms independent variable and dependent vari- able became universal in introductory psychology textbooks, and how these terms were used to define a relationship between causality and experimentation. By the 1970s, all North American psychology students were taught that an experiment consists of manipulation of an independent variable while holding all other vari- ables constant and observing the effect on a dependent variable, and that this is the best or sole method for the discovery of causes. My interest in the source of this methodological dictum lead to a number of investigations of textbook 53 54 ANDREW S. WINSTON conceptualizations of experimentation, ideas of “cause” in modern psychology, the influence of Ernst Mach’s philosophy of science, and the place of experimen- tation in social psychology (Winston, 1988, 1990, 2001; Winston & Blais, 1996; MacMartin & Winston 2000). I argued that the definition of experiment and its relation to causality was, for the most part, “home-grown” in psychology rather than imported into the discipline, though related to Machian philosophy of science in important ways. Further, I argued that this conceptualization profoundly shaped the way psychological questions were asked and answered. In this chapter, I have three aims. First, I will augment and amend aspects of my earlier work. Second, I will highlight some commonalities and differences of emphasis in Danziger’s and my analysis of change in the metalanguage. In this regard, I am grateful for the discussions that he and I have had over a number of years. Third, I examine the process of change in metalanguage by considering a case in which such a change was blocked by powerful authorities, during the same period that the contemporary definition of experiment was introduced. EARLY USE OF THE CONCEPT OF INDEPENDENT VARIABLE Between 1932 and 1934, a number of leading psychologists began to employ a new way of speaking about the “causes of behavior.” R. S. Woodworth, E. G. Boring, and E. C. Tolman, substituted the concept of the independent variable for the concept of cause, a term with a long and problematic history, accompa- nied by much metaphysical baggage. Each of these authors used this term in a slightly different way. The introduction of the concepts of independent variable and dependent variable into psychological discourse was an important event in terms of providing a common language for the discussion of investigations based on highly divergent theoretical systems. In this analysis, I was interested in how these terms came to define what an experiment was, and how this conceptualization then encouraged certain kinds of inquiry. In my previous work, I suggested that the terms independent variable and dependent variable did not appear in psychology until the 1930s (e.g., Winston & Blais, 1996). A more recent search of the expanded PsycINFO database indicated that some papers of the 1920s may already have used these phrases. For exam- ple, “independent variables” appears in the abstracts of both Culler (1927) and Heidbreder (1927). However, their use is not the same as in the 1930s: the term is used to mean “variables acting independently of each other,” rather than ex- perimentally manipulated factors. 1 Danziger (1997) noted that William James (1890/1950) had used the term “independent variable” in the Principles (I, p. 59), but here again, the meaning in context appears to be “independent of each other,” not the experimental factor which is manipulated by the experimenter. 2 These early CONTROLLING THE METALANGUAGE 55 uses of “independent variable’’ are not clearly derived from the original mathemat- ical meaning, described below. In this case, the use of the same term is misleading for the contemporary reader. But in other cases, a slightly different term is used to mean something close to the 1930s meaning of independent variable. One example of the use of a related term is from William Stanley Jevons (1874). In his influential Principles of Science? he described the nature of exper- iment in terms of active manipulation and identified the terms to be used: Almost every series of quantitative experiments is directed to obtain the relation between the different values of one quantity which is varied at will, and another quantity which is thereby caused to vary. We may conveniently distinguish these as respectively the variable and the variant, (p. 440) Both the terms “varianfi’and “variate” were commonly used for variable at the turn of the 19th century and in the early 20th century. In his highly influential Statistical Methods for Research Workers , R. A. Fisher (1925) used the terms “independent variate” and “dependent variate,” which he introduced to explain regression func- tions and their graphic representation. But he did not present this idea as a definition of experiment nor as the factor explicitly manipulated by the experimenter. The original meaning of independent variable and dependent variable had nothing to do with experimentation. The concepts of function and variable were clearly present in the work of Leibniz, although his concept of a function was certainly not identical to the modern one. The specific terms independent variable and dependent variable were introduced by John Radford Young in the Elements of the Differential Calculus (1833): “on account of this dependence of the value of the function upon that of the variable, the former, that is y, is called the dependent variable, and the latter, x , the independent variable” (p. 2). Johann Gustave Lejeune Dirichlet provided the modern definition of a function in 1837, which O’Connor and Robinson (2002) translated as follows: If a variable y is so related to a variable x that whenever a numerical value is assigned to x, there is a rule according to which a unique value of y is determined, then y is said to be a function of the independent variable x. The important feature here is that the independent and dependent variable are interchangeable: there is no implication that x is the cause of y, and the relation- ship can be expressed as y = f(x) or x = f(y). There is no requirement that the independent variable be manipulated, or that they have the asymmetrical status noted by Danziger (1987). As I have described elsewhere (Winston, 2001), it is in the writings of Ernst Mach that the connection between functions, experiment and explanation is outlined. By the 1880s, Mach was clear that the concept of a function, expressed mathematically, was to replace the metaphysically tainted con- cepts of cause and effect. Functions were purely descriptive and their economical 56 ANDREW S. WINSTON descriptive power was for Mach the only proper and useful form of scientific ex- planation. Once Mach and others began to speak of mathematical functions as the replacement for causal statements, it was natural to substitute the terms proper to functions, independent and dependent variables, for statements of cause and effect. However, it is possible to overstate the role of Mach in introducing the more general talk of variables in Psychology. As Danziger (1997) noted, texts and arti- cles on statistics already made the concept of variables familiar to psychologists. With the increasing introduction of statistics into research and teaching during the first three decades of the 20th century, variables, variates, or variants would figure prominently. The terms independent variable and dependent variable were per- fectly appropriate for any discussion involving a regression line. The literature of Applied Psychology, especially discussions of prediction, used independent vari- able in its original sense from the mathematics of functions during and after the 1930s (e.g., Wilson & Hodges, 1932). The use of these terms for prediction of a criterion measure from a test eventually caused some friction between experimen- talists and multivariate researchers as experimentalists came to use independent variable to refer only to manipulated conditions (see Winston, 1990). INDEPENDENT AND DEPENDENT VARIABLES APPEAR IN PSYCHOLOGY TEXTBOOKS In introductory textbooks, the earliest use of the terms independent variable and dependent variable to define experimentation was in Woodworth’s (1934) Psychology. In the third edition of his widely used textbook, he altered and nar- rowed the definition of “experiment” to include only studies in which a variable was explicitly manipulated: An experiment is one means of obtaining observations bearing on a definite ques- tion . . . the experimenter “controls the conditions.” He does not let things happen at random; in the ideal experiment he has all the factors under his control that have any influence on the process to be observed. The result shows him what happens under certain known conditions. He varies one factor and notes the difference that makes in the result. The rule for an ideal experiment is to control all the factors or conditions, to keep all of them constant except a single one — which is then the independent variable — and to vary this one systematically and observe the results. The results are changes in the dependent variable. When he finishes his series of experiments, he knows the changes in the dependent variable which are produced by changes in the independent variable. (1934, p. 18) Although Woodworth was the first to present the now universal textbook definition, E. G. Boring (1933e) had defined experiment as the manipulation of an independent variable in the previous year, in his Physical Dimensions of Consciousness, a book Boring designed as a tribute to E. B. Titchener: CONTROLLING THE METALANGUAGE 57 The experimental method, upon which all science rests, is, logically considered, a method of the induction of a generalized correlation by means of controlled con- comitant variations. In the simplest experiment there are always at least two terms, an independent variable and a dependent variable. The experimenter varies a and notes how b changes, or he removes a and sees if b disappears. He repeats until he is satis- fied that he has the generalization that b depends upon a. The independent variable, a, can now properly be spoken of as a cause of the dependent variable, b. (pp. 8-9) Boring gave no source for this formulation. A search of correspondence between Boring and Woodworth at both the Harvard and Columbia University archives failed to yield any discussion of this issue, although there is correspondence re- garding many other organizational and professional issues. It is not surprising that two leading figures would make a nearly simultaneous change in language. How- ever, they were not the only important actors here. Danziger (1997; Danziger & Dzinas, 1998) described how Edward C. Tolman also introduced the concept of independent variables. In his Purposive Behavior in Animals and Men , Tolman ( 1932) emphasized the language of “variables” when summarizing different systems of psychology in Chapter XXIV, “The Final Variables of Purposive Behaviorism.” What is im- portant here is that the term variables allowed Tolman to contrast individual dif- ference psychology, structuralism. Gestalt psychology, and behaviorism using a common language. I have argued previously that Tolman did not quite use the Boring/Woodworth formulation in 1932, and that he used an idea of “independent causes” which were clearly variables, without saying independent variables. This assertion was not correct: on page 405, Tolman referred to heredity and previous training as “two independent variables.” On page 406-407 it is clear that Tolman uses the terms “independent causes” and “independent variables” interchange- ably. As Danziger (1997) has argued, this is the most important feature of the introduction of variables: the term is used to describe not just a methodology but the theoretical entities of interest. Moreover, method and theory subsequently take on an isomorphism uncharacteristic of discourse in the natural sciences. In 1935, Tolman (1932/1967) wrote in “Psychology and Immediate Experi- ence” that both molecular (physiological) and molar behaviorists shared a common program of identifying the “independent or causal variables” (p. 102). He summed up his integrative position: A behaviorism seeks to write the form of the function fi which connects the dependent variable-the behavior, B-to the independent variables-stimulus, heredity, training, and physiological disequilibriums, S, H, T. and P. (p. 113) Thus Tolman emphasized the concepts of independent variables and dependent variables as a way of defining the project of psychology, and as the proper way to conceptualize the theoretical terms of interest. In addition, these terms aided in the explication of his “intervening variables,” which was a crucial move in the 58 ANDREW S. WINSTON synthesis he attempted through Purposive Behaviorism. Unlike Woodworth, he did not present these terms as a way of defining what an experiment is, but as a way of defining what an explanation of behavior would look like. There can be little doubt that Tolman’s continued use of these terms helped in their popularization. His APA presidential address of 1937, published as “Deter- miners of Behavior at a Choice Point” in the Psychological Review the next year (Tolman, 1938), the terms independent and dependent variable were featured very prominently (in figures, 2, 3, 6, 7, 8, 12, & 15) and the function relating them was said to provide the “cause.” It is interesting that by this time, the term cause had been allowed back into discussions of function, despite Ernst Mach’s attempts to eliminate this idea as freighted with metaphysical baggage (Winston, 2001). Insofar as Tolman’s position provided a unified vision for psychological inquiry, providing an analysis of the problems of behaviorism. Gestalt psychology, indi- vidual psychology and purposive psychology, Tolman’s language of independent variables, intervening variables, and dependent variables allowed psychologists of varied commitments to speak a common scientific language. Tolman was teaching at Harvard during the summer of 1932, and Skinner (1998) reported that he “saw a great deal of him” (p. 290) although Tolman (1952) did not mention this absence from Berkeley in his autobiography. Skinner sug- gested that he and Tolman were speaking about variables in a similar way at this time. Skinner’s statement of behavior as a function of a set of variables was, he thought, related to that of Tolman. However, Skinner rejected intervening variables in favor of “third variables,” such as deprivation, which altered the functional re- lationship between stimulus conditions and responding. Skinner’s (1998) retrospective account suggests that he had priority in the modern use of “variables.” In Skinner (1931) he argued that the experimental results of the study of a reflex can be expressed as the function: R — /'(.S'), or con- sidering third variables, R = f (S, A). He treated this relationship as experimentally derived by manipulation, and not merely as the statistical relationship between two sets of numbers (pp. 451-452). He did not use the terms independent variable and dependent variable, although they are clearly implied by his formulation. 4 More- over, Skinner’s philosophy of science, so heavily influenced by Mach (see Winston, 2001), emphasized the determination of functional relationships as the aim of his science of behavior. Priority claims are hardly the important issue here. What is significant is the social matrix in which such changes in language occurred and the social process by which they became codified and enshrined. Woodworth, Boring, and Tolman occupied positions of influence in the APA, by then a rapidly growing organiza- tion. Skinner was a new PhD, but outspoken and confident in his views. Although Boring found Skinner difficult and had severe criticisms of Skinner’s dissertation (see Bjork, 1993), he respected his intellectual talents and promoted Skinner’s career in a variety of ways. Skinner was able to publish his new conceptualization CONTROLLING THE METALANGUAGE 59 of the reflex with little delay, with the help of William Crazier, who was an editor of the Journal of General Psychology. Boring and Tolman were also in frequent contact, as Boring was attempting to recruit Tolman to return to Harvard, where he had received the PhD in 1915 (Innis, 1992). There were ample opportunities for discussion of general theoretical issues amongst these four important individ- uals. They in turn had numerous opportunities to encourage the formulation of all psychological problems in terms of independent and dependent variables. I do not mean to imply that a cabal was formed with any explicit plan to alter the language of psychologists, only that in conversation these individuals may have discovered collective as well as individual reasons for adopting and promoting a new discourse. FAILURE TO CHANGE METALANGUAGE: SAUL ROSENZWEIG AND Ee In order to understand the process by which a new linguistic practice is in- troduced and taken up, it may help to consider cases in which attempts to change scientific language fail. One clear attempt occurred in 1933, and provides an in- structive example in the microhistory of the regulation of language. In contrast to the introduction of independent variable and dependent variable at the same time, where no archival record of the relevant correspondence has been found, the discussions regarding this attempt to change the metalanguage are available, and can clarify the role of power and status in bringing about or inhibiting such change. Saul Rosenzweig (1907- ) became a graduate student at Harvard in 1929 and received the PhD in 1932. He had some difficulty obtaining an academic po- sition, despite an excellent record, due in part to the Depression and possibly to antisemitism (see Winston, 1998). He continued his work at the Harvard Clinic with Henry Murray. Boring (1932) described him as “top-notch intellectually” and “our best graduate this year.” In 1933, Rosenzweig published an important and often neglected paper: “The Experimental Situation as a Psychological Prob- lem.” Some forty years before the topic became fashionable, he introduced the idea that the experiment must be considered a social situation in which the elements were quite different from an experiment in chemistry. As a conscious being, the person serving as “subject” may “regulate their own reactions: they have minds of their own and are self critical. From this results the difficulty that uncontrolled experimental materials, viz., motives, may be brought into the experiment” (1933a, p. 353). Rosenzweig suggested that the subjects might engage in playing the part or role they thought was expected of them, might attempt to appear smart or compli- ant, would develop hypotheses about what the experimenter was after, and would generally behave in an active rather than passive fashion. He was concerned that neither the term subject, which had only recently become standard, nor the older